You are on page 1of 44

No.

590 April 11, 2007


�������

In Pursuit of Happiness Research


Is It Reliable? What Does It Imply for Policy?
by Will Wilkinson

Executive Summary

“Happiness research” studies the correlates of cannot be relied on as an authoritative source for
subjective well-being, generally through survey empirical information about happiness, which, in
methods. A number of psychologists and social any case, is not a simple empirical phenomenon
scientists have drawn upon this work recently to but a cultural and historical moving target. Yet,
argue that the American model of relatively limit- even if we accept the data of happiness research at
ed government and a dynamic market economy face value, few of the alleged redistributive policy
corrodes happiness, whereas Western European implications actually follow from the evidence.
and Scandinavian-style social democracies pro- The data show that neither higher rates of gov-
mote it. This paper argues that happiness ernment redistribution nor lower levels of income
research in fact poses no threat to the relatively inequality make us happier, whereas high levels of
libertarian ideals embodied in the U.S. socioeco- economic freedom and high average incomes are
nomic system. Happiness research is seriously among the strongest correlates of subjective well-
hampered by confusion and disagreement about being. Even if we table the damning charges of
the definition of its subject as well as the limita- questionable science and bad moral philosophy,
tions inherent in current measurement tech- the American model still comes off a glowing suc-
niques. In its present state happiness research cess in terms of happiness.

_____________________________________________________________________________________________________
Will Wilkinson is a policy analyst at the Cato Institute and is managing editor of Cato Unbound.
Layard’s belief Layard is sufficiently confident in the qual-
that happiness Introduction: ity of happiness research to bless it as a “new
Is the United States a science.” It is claimed that we now know, at
research supports Failure? long last, what really makes people happy.
the policies of Geoffrey Miller, a psychologist at the Univers-
“There is a paradox at the heart of our lives,” ity of New Mexico, writes: “In the last ten years,
more heavily writes Richard Layard, head of the London psychology has finally started to deliver the
regulated markets School of Economics Center for Economic goods—hard facts about what causes human
and a more Performance and member of the British House happiness.”6 Scholars like Layard have not hes-
of Lords. “As Western societies have got richer,” itated to base dramatic policy recommenda-
egalitarian Layard tells us, “their people have become no tions on our alleged newfound facts. Layard
welfare state has happier.”1 Psychologist of happiness David argues, for example, that a government that
become a sort of Myers opens his book, The American Paradox, cares about the pursuit of happiness will levy
on a Dickensian note: “It is the worst of times, higher taxes on income, impose strict controls
conventional and the best of times.” We owe the “worst of on advertising and marketing, mandate gener-
wisdom among times,” according to Myers, to “radical individ- ous periods of paid parental leave, and imple-
ualism” and “libertarianism,” both civil and ment “radical” mandatory public school
those who study economic.2 Journalist Gregg Easterbrook puts courses covering aspects of life generally left to
happiness. it this way: “We live in a favored age and do not parents aiming “to produce a happier genera-
feel favored.”3 His bestselling book, The Progress tion of adults than the current generation,”
Paradox, set out to explain “why capitalism and and much else besides.7
liberal democracy, both of which justify them- Layard’s belief that happiness research sup-
selves on the grounds that they produce the ports the policies of more heavily regulated
greatest happiness for the greatest number, markets and a more thoroughgoing egalitarian
leave so much dissatisfaction in their wake.”4 welfare state is by no means unique. Indeed, it
All of those works and many more tap into appears to have become a sort of conventional
a rapidly growing body of research on the cor- wisdom among those who study happiness. In
relates of human happiness. Starting roughly an academic paper about the evolutionary psy-
with University of Southern California econo- chology of happiness (and not about the politics
mist Richard Easterlin’s watershed 1973 paper of happiness), psychiatrist Rudolph Nesse, ref-
showing that average happiness levels report- erencing the work of Layard and Cornell
ed by Americans had not risen for decades University economist Robert Frank, reports in
despite a doubling in average incomes, econo- passing what he takes to be the established
mists, sociologists, and psychologists have political implications of happiness research:
been busy canvassing the world, handing out
“life satisfaction” surveys and customized On a social and political level, it is
“experience sampling” Palm Pilots and then abundantly clear that certain policies
running the data through computers with can increase average SWB [subjective
cutting-edge statistical software to tease out well-being] in a society. More equitable
the determinants of a satisfying life.5 income distribution is highly correlated
How important is wealth to happiness? with the average level of well-being in a
How important is marriage? Parenthood? Job society, and high taxes on high incomes
satisfaction? Leisure time? Health? The rate and luxury goods would result in only
of unemployment? The rate of economic infinitesimal decrements in the posi-
growth? Democratic institutions? Social safe- tional pleasures provided by luxury
ty nets? The happiness researchers even have goods. Most democratic societies seem
their own journal, The Journal of Happiness unable, however, to enact laws based on
Studies, where all of this, and more, is analyzed this knowledge to increase the well-
at length. being in their societies.8

2
Notre Dame University political scientist leader in “behavioral economics” at Carnegie
Benjamin Radcliff argues that market-orient- Mellon University, “doesn’t see how anybody
ed societies are by nature corrosive to happi- could study happiness and not find himself
ness and that large welfare states are the rem- leaning left politically.”13
edy. Publishing in his field’s most prominent Perhaps the most compelling left-leaning
journal, Radcliff claims that the accumulated arguments based on happiness research are
data suggest: those, such as Robert Frank’s in his book
Luxury Fever, which de-emphasize the impor-
Life satisfaction should increase as we tance of absolute material wealth to happiness
move from less to more social democra- and stress instead the importance of relative
tic welfare states. More generally, life position in the distribution of income and
satisfaction should vary positively with social status. Whereas happiness research has
the dominance in government of politi- shown a flat trend in happiness over time, it
cal parties committed to the social also shows that at any time wealthier people are
democratic program of limiting human more likely to say they are happy. However, so
dependence on the market.9 the argument goes, if we all run harder to pull
ahead in the race for the benefits of higher rel-
Elsewhere Radcliff argues that “the more we ative standing, those ahead will just run hard-
Like Layard,
supplement the cold efficiency of the free mar- er too. In the end, the frantic pace will have left Nesse, and
ket system with interventions that reduce us all harried and exhausted, and average hap- Radcliff, many
poverty, insecurity and inequality, the more we piness will have remained unchanged.
improve the quality of life.”10 Like Layard, “Every time [some people] raise their rela- believe that
Nesse, and Radcliff, many others believe it has tive income (which they like),” Layard writes, certain policies—
been established that certain policies—policies “they lower the relative income of other people
that would make the United States more like (which those people dislike). This is an ‘exter-
policies that
Sweden or France—would enhance our happi- nal disbenefit’ imposed on others, a form of would make the
ness. “The utilitarian argument for the rich giv- physical pollution.”14 Layard’s proposed solu- United States
ing more of their money to the poor is now sci- tion is a tax on “the polluting activity” or, as
entifically irrefutable,” writes Geoffrey Miller, economists call it, the “negative externality.” more like Sweden
“but few journalists have recognized that revo- The polluting activity here is nothing less than or France—would
lutionary implication.”11 Swarthmore College your and my working hard to make more enhance our
psychologist Barry Schwartz, writing in the money. But, if it is relative standing that mat-
New Republic, says that thanks to happiness ters, the increase in total wealth will not happiness.
research “we now know there is some signifi- increase happiness on average. There will
cant subset of people likely to be made better always be a top half and bottom half. A tax
off through heavier taxation, and that these that reduces the monetary benefits of labor
people reside at the top end of the wealth dis- and so encourages everyone to ease up in uni-
tribution.” Schwartz continues: son will slow the pace of life and reduce
incomes. This, the argument goes, will do no
Given that a concern for people’s welfare harm to happiness, but the time and energy
has traditionally been one of the chief freed to pursue the pleasures of family, friends,
moral objections to taxing wealth (at and leisure will do a world of good.
least among those sympathetic to redis- If we must push ourselves ever harder
tribution in principle), a policy of heavier merely to keep up, then it is easy to suspect
taxation for the very wealthy may be the that the output of increased economic pro-
only moral course of action.12 duction will not actually contribute to our
happiness. We end up with nothing but super-
An article on happiness research in the New fluous abundance, the side-effect of a mad
York Times reports that George Loewenstein, a dash that does nothing but wear us down and

3
hollow us out, even as it sedates us with the The task of this paper is to examine the
spurious satisfactions of unending novelty. state of happiness research and grade the per-
This is a powerful and compelling line of formance of the United States on its own
reasoning, in the light of which it becomes test. Has the nation’s relatively dynamic,
easy to understand why the importance of competitive, free-market system failed us in
economic growth has taken a beating by a the pursuit of happiness? Has “science”
number of prominent happiness scholars. In shown that the ideals of free markets and
an article entitled “The Hippies Were Right limited government deserve retirement? If we
about Happiness,” Warwick University eco- would in fact be happier as denizens of an
nomics professor Andrew Oswald writes: egalitarian welfare state on the model of
European social democracies, it may seem
Routinely derided, the ideas of these that only the ignorant or spiteful would try
down-to-earth philosophers are being to stand in the way of happier lives and a bet-
confirmed by new statistical work by ter grade on the American test. So we have to
psychologists and economists. . . . Once ask: Would we be right to scrap our current
a country has filled its larders, there is no system and start over?
point in that nation becoming richer. . . . The aim of this paper is to demonstrate that
Economists’ faith in the value of growth happiness research poses no threat to U.S.
is diminishing. That is a good thing and ideals as they have been historically interpreted
will slowly make its way down into the and are embodied (albeit imperfectly) in our
minds of tomorrow’s politicians.15 present socioeconomic system. Happiness
research is seriously hampered by confusion
The Declaration of Independence states that and disagreement about the definition of its
“all men are created equal,” vested with rights to subject as well as the limitations inherent in
“Life, Liberty, and the pursuit of Happiness.” current measurement techniques. Happiness
The apparent consensus among happiness research in its present state cannot be relied on
researchers strongly suggests that America has as an authoritative source for empirical infor-
failed to live up to its founding ideals. mation about happiness, which, in any case, is
Happiness research may seem to pose a grave not a simple empirical phenomenon but a cul-
threat to the legitimacy of the relatively libertar- tural and historical moving target. Further-
ian American political-economic model. more, happiness is not the only element of
The threat hits home with a vengeance human well-being or of a valuable life. At the
when we recall that the Declaration was not very least, believing that it is has no standing as
just a statement of national ideals but an a scientific proposition, and there is no liberal
Even if we put incendiary argument aimed at the justifica- moral justification for holding up happiness as
tion of rebellion—a radical case for overthrow- the sole standard for evaluating policy in a con-
aside charges of ing the government. According to the Dec- tentiously pluralistic society. Yet the problems
questionable laration, “whenever any Form of Government with the political uses of happiness research
science and becomes destructive of these ends” (i.e., life, run deeper than methodology. Even if we grant
liberty, and the pursuit of happiness) “it is the that the findings of happiness research do shed
bad moral Right of the People to alter or abolish it,” and some light on the state of human well-being,
philosophy, the replace it with a government they feel sure will few of the main alleged implications for public
United States still “effect their Safety and Happiness.” In other policy actually follow from a fair reading of the
words, if a government actively interferes with evidence. In a nutshell: even if we put aside
comes off as a its citizens’ pursuit of happiness, it has no charges of questionable science and bad moral
glowing success legitimate authority, and citizens are justified philosophy, the United States still comes off as
in scrapping it and starting over. A failing a glowing success in terms of happiness. If any
in terms of grade on the “American test” of happiness is a nation deserves an “A” on the “American test,”
happiness. call for massive reform, if not outright revolt. the United States does.

4
Though the putative implications of hap- together, how happy would you say you are: Surveys are
piness research touch on almost all areas of very happy, quite happy, not very happy, or not fairly blunt
life and public policy, this paper focuses on at all happy?” is a typical question that appears
three major claims: on the widely used World Values Survey.16 instruments for
Other surveys, such as those conducted by the probing into
(1) The relatively greater dynamism of the National Opinion Research Center, use slight-
U.S. market economy and the relative- ly different wording and a three-point scale.
people’s psyches.
ly smaller scope of the U.S. welfare There are also multi-item surveys, such as the
state are bad for happiness, and we one included in the Midlife Development
would be happier with European-style Inventory, that ask about the frequency of pos-
social democracy. itive and negative feelings17 and the popular
(2) The importance of relative position to multi-item Satisfaction with Life Scale created
happiness provides a justification for by University of Illinois psychologist Ed
higher taxes on income and/or con- Diener.18 Some surveys, such as the Eurobar-
sumption. ometer survey, ask how “satisfied,” instead of
(3) Economic growth is unimportant to how “happy,” the respondent is with his or her
happiness, and measures of social wel- life.
fare such as GDP per capita (or growth Though broad-brush surveys dominate
in GDP per capita) should be replaced the field of happiness research at present,
or at least augmented with measures there are other, more fine-grained self-report
of happiness. techniques. The experience sampling method
(ESM) was pioneered by psychologist Mihaly
Before explaining why each of these claims Csikszentmihalyi, best known for his work
is false, I will discuss how happiness research is on peak experience or “flow.”19 ESM equips
currently conducted, what it says, and why it volunteers with beepers or specially outfitted
tells us less than its defenders think. handheld computers programmed to sound
an alert at random intervals throughout the
day, at which point the volunteer is supposed
The Limits of Happiness to makes note of what he is doing and how
Research he feels while doing it. Because ESM can be
very expensive for large samples, recent stud-
Happiness research is a label for a wide ies have begun to use the Day Reconstruction
range of research programs that aim to uncov- Method, created by economics Nobel Prize-
er the correlates or causal determinants of winning psychologist Daniel Kahneman and
happiness, life-satisfaction, or subjective well- others, as a substitute.20 Volunteers in DRM
being (commonly abbreviated as SWB). For studies are asked to spend time at the end of
the most part, happiness researchers—usually the day recalling and recording their activi-
economists, psychologists, and sociologists— ties during the day along with what they were
rely on data gathered from large surveys in feeling while performing them.
which people report how they are feeling, as Even more promising, the development of
well as how much money they make, how medical diagnostic technology such as brain
many children they have, what kind of job imaging and the isolation of hormones in
they have, and so forth. Researchers then blood samples now allows us to measure
search for patterns in relationships between directly the organic underpinnings of good
answers about happiness and answers about and bad feelings. There is a wide array of neu-
money, children, work, and so forth, using a rotransmitters and hormones, such as
wide variety of statistical techniques. dopamine, serotonin, oxytocin, cortisol, pro-
Surveys are fairly blunt instruments for lactin, and many more that may contribute to
probing into people’s psyches. “Taken all good and bad feelings. There are a few studies

5
that attempt to directly measure the physical don’t simply get used to psychologically, that
basis of well-being, but, so far, they are very don’t diminish in light of shifting aspirations,
few—in large part because they are very expen- and that aren’t sensitive to social comparison.
sive. The recent work of University of The absolute effect hypothesis is not an expla-
Wisconsin psychologist Carol Ryff and her nation of the Easterlin Paradox, but rather a
team of investigators stands out as an example denial of it. In other words, it is the claim that
of happiness research that integrates brain happiness has increased significantly with
imaging and biochemical evidence with survey income and wealth.
research.21 Though such research efforts are It is not my purpose here to sort out the rel-
difficult, time-consuming, and expensive, they ative explanatory power of the “adaptation-set
promise to advance our understanding of point” and “aspiration adjustment” hypothe-
happiness considerably and deserve greater ses. This paper does argue, however, that there
attention and emulation. is some absolute effect of wealth and income
Much of the happiness literature is occu- not subject to adaptation and aspiration shift-
pied with examining the relative merits of ing and that the importance of relative posi-
three hypotheses (or combinations thereof) tion is dramatically overblown. But if there are
that seek to explain the so-called “Easterlin continuous real effects of increasing material
Paradox”—the fact that average self-reported well-being, then why are they so hard to see?
happiness has not risen with average income.
The “adaptation-set point” hypothesis says Problems with Surveys
that each of us has a settled disposition to The first question that occurs to most
Doesn’t feel a certain way (our largely genetically people when encountering survey-based hap-
everyone have determined happiness “set point”) and that piness research is whether everyone thinks of
we quickly “adapt” or habituate” psychologi- “happiness” in the same way and whether we
his own notion cally to both pleasurable and painful events, judge our own level of satisfaction according
of happiness? reverting eventually to that usual set point.22 to the same standards. Doesn’t everyone have
Isn’t this way The “aspiration adjustment” hypothesis— his own notion of happiness? Isn’t this way of
Easterlin’s own favored explanation—makes measuring subjective well-being too . . . sub-
of measuring sense of the flat happiness trend by noting jective? Happiness scholars generally point to
subjective well- that people tend to raise their aspirations as the same small set of studies that show some
soon as they have met their old ones. If self- correlation with self-reported happiness and
being too . . . reported happiness is an individual’s assess- other things we might imagine to be objec-
subjective? ment of their position relative to their aspira- tive manifestations of happiness, such as
tions, a penchant for constantly “shifting the increased blood-flow in certain parts of the
goal-posts” will ensure people rarely say they brain, smiling a lot, or being rated as happy
are getting happier.23 Last, as we’ve already by one’s friends and family. However, these
noted, there is the “relative position” hypoth- checks on the validity of happiness surveys
esis, which claims that self-reported happi- are only as good as the thinking behind
ness is a function of our relative position in a them, and some of the thinking isn’t very
social hierarchy. Since that hierarchy is often impressive. For example, people in some cul-
identified with income distribution, the rela- tures just seem to smile more than others,
tive position hypothesis is taken by many to and there is evidence that “authentic” smiles
explain why increases in average income function more as social cues than as raw
don’t correlate strongly with increases in physical expressions of individual emotion,
average happiness.24 so it is hard to know how much confirmation
Opposed to each of these theses is the of survey data is provided by noting that peo-
“absolute effect” hypothesis, which states that ple who say they are happier smile more.25
increases in material well-being have real and Other happiness researchers dispute the
lasting effects on happiness—effects that we implied objection by invoking the law of

6
large numbers, which guarantees that ran- reported happiness than would be expected
dom variations are washed out with an ade- from their levels of wealth and the quality of
quately large and representative sample.26 their political institutions, whereas many
But a great deal of variation seems not to Latin American countries post what seem to
be random at all. For example, it is not clear be inflated happiness scores, a difference they
that all cultures understand “happiness” the admit “could be influenced by response bias-
same way Americans, or Westerners more es rather than actual experience. For example,
generally, do. And, if it needs to be said, the the Japanese [who score unusually low on
properties of being American or being surveys] might not want to stand out from
Chinese, for example, are not randomly dis- their group by saying they are very happy.”30
tributed throughout the human population. They note that psychological and cultural
Cultural characteristics can matter for the “norms for feeling emotions, and the desire
way people respond to surveys, even in the to fulfill the high expectations of others, can
unlikely event that cultural differences break also have an effect” on happiness surveys.31
along political boundaries. Of course, there is also cultural hetero-
With a few notable exceptions, it has so far geneity within societies, with some societies
been rare to encounter any acknowledge- being more heterogeneous than others. It
ment that survey measures track anything would seem to follow that nations like the
but a universal and ahistorical form of expe- United States, which absorb high numbers of
rience or that different languages might immigrants from every part of the world, will
express these experiences differently. yield samples that contain a large degree of
Australian National University linguist nonrandom cultural variation in the way
Anna Wierzbicka—perhaps the world’s lead- happiness survey questions are interpreted
ing authority on the ways different languages and answered. It’s worth emphasizing again
express emotion—says, “The glibness with that the political boundaries of modern
which linguistic differences are at times states may or may not fall along national,
denied in the current literature on happiness ethnic, or cultural lines.
can be quite astonishing.”27 According to Cultural heterogeneity aside, economist
Wierzbicka, “It is an illusion . . . to think that Andrew Clark and coauthors have found that
the English words happy and happiness have there is, in any case, a good deal of patterned
exact semantic equivalents in Chinese or, for diversity not only in the way people within
that matter, in other European languages.”28 societies translate variables like income into
She does not argue that cross-cultural and happiness, but in the way they express their
linguistic comparisons of self-reported sub- happiness level in speech and on self-report-
jective states are hopeless, but that cross-cul- ed surveys.32 The English
tural and linguistic comparisons of self- Suppose, for example, you and I both
reported happiness are. The English words make $50,000 per year, and we both report words “happy”
“happy” and “happiness” do not have exact our happiness level as a 7 on a scale from 1 to and “happiness”
counterparts in every language, and they 10. However, the fact that we circled the same
express sets of cultural expectations and number on the survey guarantees neither
do not have exact
ideals about the experience and expression of that we are equally happy nor that income counterparts in
emotions that are not universal. “To be able affects our happiness equally. Suppose fur- every language,
to interpret self-reports across cultures,” she ther that your level of satisfaction at $50,000
writes, “one needs a methodology for explor- a year is what mine would be at $70,000 (hold- and they express
ing cultural norms that may guide the inter- ing other things equal). So I am, in fact, less sets of cultural
viewees in their responses.”29 satisfied than you are with the same income expectations and
Psychologists Ed Diener and Shigehiro and life as a whole (since other things are
Oishi find that Confucian-influenced Asian equal). However, for some reason (cultural ideals that are
nations report lower levels of average self- differences in the expression of feelings, dif- not universal.

7
The way people ferences in goals or expectations, different diverse populations risks producing empiri-
report their personality types, or whatever), our internal cal results that are false for everybody.”35
standards for translating feelings into lan- In their study, Clark and his team “show
happiness is guage differ, so we end up reporting the same that people are different,” and not randomly
highly sensitive level of happiness despite the fact we do not so, as they tend to fall into different classes of
feel the same. happiness survey response in predictable pat-
to context, Given the same input to experience (e.g., a terns based on a number of personal and
threatening the certain income, a certain number of hours demographic variables. Though they are
reliability of spent watching television, etc.), people can unable to tease out which people fall into
feel the same thing but talk about it different- each class due to language-squishing and/or
surveys. ly. Harvard psychologist Dan Gilbert calls experience stretching, they are able to
this “language-squishing.” Or people can feel “strongly reject the hypothesis that individu-
differently, but talk about it the same way. als carry out these joint transformations
Gilbert call this “experience stretching.” “The [from income to experience and experience
fundamental problem in the science of expe- to self-reported happiness] in the same way.”
rience,” Gilbert writes, This leads them to conclude that “aggregat-
ing data across diverse populations may be a
is that if either the language-squishing dangerous practice.” They write that “indi-
or the experience-stretching hypothe- viduals who seem to fall naturally into a
sis is correct, then every one of us may number of different classes differ in ways
have a different mapping of what we that are far more complicated” than those
say—and because subjective experi- picked up by studies that control for the
ences can be shared only by saying, the effect of simple individual differences on
true nature of those experiences can- happiness.36
not be perfectly measured.33 In addition to systematic differences
between individuals, the way people report
Gilbert attempts to solve the problem by their happiness is highly sensitive to context,
appealing to the law of large numbers: “when threatening the reliability of surveys. In a
[the number of individuals in the sample] series of papers, philosopher Dan Haybron
becomes two hundred or two thousand, the has argued that life satisfaction judgments
different calibrations of these individuals are highly labile and perspective dependent.
begin to cancel one another out.”34 As we’ve Quite appropriately, people have different
noted, the law of large numbers works when standards for assessing how well things are
it washes out random variations in properties going, and they may employ different stan-
that are not systematically correlated with dards in different sorts of circumstances. The
one another (i.e., that are “independent.”) way we answer a question about how satis-
However, if variation is nonrandom within a fied we are with life as a whole will depend on
group—if, say, tendencies of language-squish- the standard that happens to be active at the
ing and experience-stretching tend to associ- time. “We are all familiar,” Haybron writes,
ate with other nonrandom properties—the
overall average may be largely useless, convey- with the tendency we have to waver
ing inaccurate information about every sub- between appraising our circumstances
group. It may be that the average weight of a by comparison with the less fortunate,
group of Chihuahuas and mastiffs (we don’t with certain of our peers, or with the
know how many of each) is 36 pounds, but more fortunate. Compared to A things
it’s not very helpful to know this. This sort of might be going swimmingly, but com-
mixed sample is what Clark and coauthor’s pared to B—or one’s hopes, aspirations,
have in mind when they note that “our expectations, past experience, etc.—one’s
results suggest that the blind aggregation of situation might be dismal.37

8
In an award-winning paper, psychologist you’ve experienced habituation. If you buy a
Michael Hagerty demonstrates that partici- new high-definition television, you’ll get an
pants in self-reported happiness surveys do initial boost in pleasure as you marvel at the
not all use the same internal standard for clarity of the picture, but after a while you’ll
reporting their life satisfaction. Some report simply forget what it was like not to see
how well they are doing relative to their aspi- Simon, Randy, and Paula’s pores. As former
rations, or how they just happen to be feeling American Psychological Association presi-
at the moment, but most report their life sat- dent Martin Seligman writes: “This process
isfaction with an eye to how well they are [of habituation] is an inviolable neurological
doing relative to their perceived peer group. fact of life. Neurons are wired to respond to
However, Hagerty shows that the standard of novel events, and not to fire if the events do
judgment people use when reporting their not provide new information.”41 Although
level of happiness is contextual and malleable, greater income may purchase conveniences,
and that we can easily switch our frame of ref- fancy cars, and neat gadgets, you simply get
erence when primed to do so. When asked to used to them and eventually revert to your
report how well they are doing relative to their ex-ante happiness “set point.”
own and their parents’ past, self-reported happi- Hedonic or affective adaptation may be
ness levels rose dramatically.38 natural selection’s way of allocating scarce
When asked to
Even more confounding, it is possible that attention and motivation efficiently, reward- report how well
we do not always have ready or reliable access ing the organism for deploying its resources they are doing
to the quality of our own subjective states. to new stimuli requiring immediate atten-
After summarizing the various forms of access tion.42 Furthermore, the dissipation of both relative to their
and reporting biases to which psychological good and bad feelings is likely to keep the own and their
research has shown we are subject, Dan organism motivated. We’d starve if we never
Haybron concludes: “We cannot assume that again became hungry after eating one great
parents’ past, self-
people are reliable judges of their own affective meal. And if the satisfaction of our last reported
states. In fact I suspect something stronger: achievement never faded, there might not be happiness levels
that pervasive [affective ignorance] is not just a a next achievement. The upshot is that there
possibility, but the reality.”39 How is it possible is no “happiness bank” in which to accumu- rose dramatically.
they cannot always accurately judge our own late and continually experience an ever
inner lives? Psychological theorists Randy J. greater sum of good feelings. It seems to be a
Larsen and Barbara L. Fredrickson argue: condition of our biological emergence that
happiness is evanescent. Mark Twain nailed
If some emotional episodes are either it when one of his characters says, “as soon as
outside phenomenal awareness or not the novelty is over and the force of the con-
represented in working memory, par- trast dulled, it ain’t happiness any longer,
ticipants will be unable to perceive or and you have to get something fresh.”43
recognize the feeling state accurately The phenomenon of adaptation cannot
and, as a consequence, unable to pro- only help explain why average levels of self-
vide accurate self-reports.40 reported happiness have tended not to rise,
but it can also explain how the trend in self-
A major problem in this regard is the reported happiness could remain flat even if
human capacity for habituation, mentioned the quality of experience was improving (or
earlier as one of the three explanations for deteriorating). Adaptation may affect atten-
the Easterlin Paradox. If you’ve ever jumped tion as well as feelings. Because the mind
into a swimming pool, cried out from the seeks novelty and quickly shunts off anti-
shock of the cold, and then, just a few min- quated stimuli into the background of
utes later, found yourself splashing around awareness, it is possible that we not only stop
happily, no longer feeling cold at all, then noticing after a while how great our new

9
Audi looks, or how bad the paper mill smells, many ergonomic adjustments to their
but also that we stop noticing the quality of workstations, and were markedly less
our own experiential states once they, too, persistent in efforts to solve difficult
have become old news. We stop paying atten- puzzles afterwards. Yet the researchers
tion especially if a change in feeling persists. were surprised to find no differences in
We might feel simply terrific and not notice, reports of perceived stress—specifically,
since we almost always feel terrific. reports about the extent to which sub-
Besides the fact that most of us don’t pay jects felt “bothered, worried, relaxed,
attention to how well we are doing compared frustrated, unhappy, contented, [or]
to how things were in the past, we aren’t usu- tense. . . . It seems likely that given
ally mindful of just how well scientific and enough time, the experienced office
economic progress has rooted out many small workers . . . ceased to notice the unpleas-
and not-so-small aggravations and pains from ant effects of the noise. Yet it also seems
life. Prior to the advent of modern sanitation plausible that the noise affected not
and medicine, multitudes suffered from fre- only subjects’ physiological responses
quent low-grade bacterial infections and wan- and behavior, but the hedonic quality of
dered around with toothaches and other their experience as well: they experi-
chronic maladies.44 It seems unlikely that peo- enced more stress, had a less pleasant
ple simply adapted to it and didn’t really feel time of it, than they would have without
lousy after a while. It seems rather more likely the noise.
that they felt lousy all along, but adapted atten-
tionally rather than experientially. They simply If the contemporary developed world is like a
stopped paying that much attention to the less-noisy office, we may in fact feel better
constant dull pain, irritation, and fatigue, without knowing enough to say so.45
because there was no new information in it. So For all the ink spilled over the Easterlin
if you had asked how they were feeling, they Paradox, it is puzzling how seldom happiness
might have told you they felt fine, because researchers point out that while the scales on
they weren’t paying attention by “design.” happiness surveys are bounded, there is no
Similar points can be made regarding all upper limit on the growth of income. This
the comforts and conveniences made avail- should be an obvious source of possible dis-
able during the past half-century of flat self- tortion in the happiness data. Suppose for a
reported happiness levels. It is conceivable moment that happiness does rise continuously
that none of this has actually made a positive with income, and suppose further that people
difference in the quality of people’s subjective do not readjust their representations of the
experience, but it seems more likely that we happiness scale as they become wealthier. In
simply don’t realize just how good we feel. that case, there will be a point at which the
We aren’t usually This is one reason it is crucial for happiness entire population has finally climbed into the
mindful of just research to focus more on the biochemical top happiness bracket. From that moment
correlates of good and bad feelings in order forward, average happiness must remain flat,
how well scientific to create a more trustworthy picture of how simply as an artifact of the bounded scale, even
and economic well we actually feel. if people continue to become happier as they
progress has The usefulness of more objective, organic continue to become richer. However, in light
measures is illustrated by a study reported by of the fact that people have quite limited
rooted out many Dan Haybron in his compelling, carefully access to the facts about how happy they are, it
small and not-so- argued paper, “Do We Know How Happy We seems almost certain that we have no idea how
small aggravations Are?”: happy it is possible to become—whether for
humans in general or as individuals. With no
and pains from [Subjects in a noisy office] showed ele- knowledge of the real, empirical upper bound
life. vated epinephrine levels, made half as on happiness, and, a fortiori, no knowledge of

10
the relationship of one’s feelings to the objec- However, it is not even necessary to accept Happiness
tive limit, it seems individuals have no alterna- the existence of values other than happiness to seems to be
tive but to construct an internal representation reach this result, since happiness itself seems
of the happiness scale on the basis of historical to be multidimensional and plural in consti- multidimensional
and cultural convention (“Under what condi- tution, having complex biological underpin- and plural in
tions do people around here generally say they nings. First, neuroscientific studies have estab-
are happy?”) and on the basis of some kind of lished that good and bad feelings do not exist
constitution,
self or social comparison (“Everybody says on a single continuum—an increment of plea- having complex
Barb is really happy, and I guess I’m doing a lit- sure does not cancel out an equal increment of biological
tle less well than Barb,” or “I feel a lot better pain—and it is possible to feel happy and sad
than I did last year.”) simultaneously.47 Second, the fact that so underpinnings.
Even if happiness (as opposed to survey many different hormones and neurotransmit-
measures thereof) has no fixed upper limit, ters are causally implicated in different posi-
increasing individual levels of happiness may tive and negative feelings creates the possibili-
come at an increasing individual cost. Such, ty of what Dan Haybron calls an “affect-type
at any rate, is the suggestion made by Nobel bias.” “When judging how happy we are, for
Prize-winning economist Gary Becker and instance, we may focus primarily on affects
his coauthor Luis Rayo in a paper modeling that fall along the joy-sadness dimension
the evolutionary logic of adaptation.46 Becker rather than on those, say, along the anxious-
and Rayo are thinking of “evolutionary cost,” calm dimension,” Haybron writes.48
in the context of inclusive biological fitness, When there are so many things going on
in order to demonstrate the possibility that at once biochemically and experientially, we
natural selection might lead to preferences cannot pay attention to it all, and we may
that limit the pursuit of happiness past a cer- find some types of good and bad feelings
tain point. But it is possible to think of the more immediately available to awareness, or
increasing marginal cost of happiness in more relevant for judgments about happi-
terms of personal cost if we accept that there ness. Further, we may not know how much
are values other than happiness, and there- weight to put on different dimensions of feel-
fore, do not assume that happiness is the ing for the purposes of generating a single
only “benefit” that may be of value to indi- summed judgment about our subjective well-
viduals. (Indeed, Becker and Rayo’s argument being. Imagine, for example, a man concur-
sheds light on why evolution would lead us rently experiencing anxiety about missing an
to value things that are in competition with appointment, satisfaction from a delicious
happiness.) In that case, there may be a limit lunch, excitement at having won the office
to how much people they are willing to “pay” fantasy football league, disappointment in
to become happier. If someone has reached his daughter’s poor report card, and a shoot-
the point at which a marginal “unit” of hap- ing pain in his trick knee. If he’s going to
piness costs too much in terms of other val- manage to make a judgment at all about how
ues, then he will be optimally happy according well he’s feeling, he is going to need one
to his individual preferences. If the cost of dimension of feeling to stand out especially
happiness, and willingness to pay for a mar- in attention (i.e., he may need an affect-type
ginal unit, varies from person to person, or bias), lest he get stuck in the quagmire of
from society to society, an individual’s place determining just how much postprandial
relative to his optimal upper limit may be dif- delight weighs against paternal frustration.
ferent than his place on some imagined If there is no single common currency of
objective scale. Therefore, one person may be affective experience, and feeling better on one
happier than another relative to some objec- affective dimension sometimes come at the
tive happiness scale, yet further away from expense of feeling better on another, then it is
his own optimal upper bound. inevitable that people will have highly vari-

11
able and individualized exchange rates Happiness are actually measuring? Here is the
between dimensions of affect. Optimal hap- heart of the problem. Is happiness really
piness for one person, given her valuation of something subjective? Is it simply a matter of
different dimensions of affect, is going to pleasure, a positive feeling? One can at least
look very different from optimal happiness hope it is not.”49
for another. Notice that this is the case even The panoply of measurement techniques
if we accept the dubious claim that only hap- and the multiplicity of dimensions of good
piness is of value. and bad feeling force us to follow Annas and
At this point, the very idea of objective ask pointedly what it is exactly that research-
happiness scales seems to dissolve into a ers are attempting to measure. To say we are
morass of confusion. Can there be a determi- trying to size up “happiness” is to say some-
nate way to locate the upper and lower thing, but, unfortunately, not very much.
bounds of the happiness scale if, for example, Because, well, what is happiness?
happiness is multidimensional, and the posi- While surveying the happiness literature, it
tions on the anxiety-calm dimension have no is easy to get the impression that somebody—
set value relative to positions on the sadness- maybe even everybody—knows the answer. But
joy dimension? Although we may be able use- if questions have sizes, then this is something
The panoply of fully to measure individual dimensions of like the Everest of questions. Its unavoidable
measurement happiness—whether it be calm, joy, sensual shadow falls over the entire enterprise of hap-
techniques and pleasure, self-esteem, a sense of self-efficacy piness research, and accounts of successful
and control, and so forth—we may not be expeditions give conflicting descriptions of
the multiplicity of able to measure happiness as such because the view from the summit. So far I have acqui-
dimensions of Mother Nature has nowhere posted a table of esced in the indiscriminate use of the term
exchange rates between the various kinds of “happiness,” but the various measurement
good and bad feelings and mental states that are ingredi- techniques track different, if overlapping,
feeling force us to ents in individual conceptions of happiness. phenomena. Furthermore, it is unclear that
ask what it is Happiness—as a simple, universal, unitary any of these techniques measure whatever it is
phenomenon—simply may not be out there that we are thinking about when we think
exactly that in the world for the scientist to find. about how much we would like to be happy.
researchers are In technical language, the question
attempting to What Are We Trying to Measure? amounts to this: what is the dependent vari-
Julia Annas, an eminent historian of able—the target of elucidation and explana-
measure. ancient philosophy and author of The Morality tion—in happiness research? Here are the main
of Happiness—a scholarly book exploring possibilities:
ancient Greek conceptions of happiness—dis-
covered one day that she had been added to a (1) Life satisfaction
bibliography of happiness researchers on the A cognitive judgment about overall life
World Database of Happiness website. quality relative to expectations.
Browsing around the site, she was discour- (2) Experiential or “hedonic” quality
aged to find nothing that resembled the con- The quantity of pleasure net of pain in the
ception of “happiness as achievement” she stream of subjective experience.
had developed from decades of studying (3) Happiness
Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics. However dis- Some state yet to be determined, but con-
couraged, in the end Annas was not surprised ceived as a something not exhausted by
“that if you rush to look for empirical mea- life satisfaction or the quality of experien-
sures of an unanalyzed ‘subjective’ phenome- tial states.
non, the result will be confusion and banality. (4) Well-being or welfare
After all,” she continues, “what is it that the Objectively how well life is going for the
social scientists on the World Database of person living it.

12
The relationship between these four con- reports after the fact systematically fail to reflect
ceptions in the happiness literature is exceed- the actual average intensity of pain they had
ingly complex. And the views of prominent reported on a pain scale every 60 seconds during
happiness scholars fail spectacularly to con- the procedure.53 “The retrospective evaluations
verge on a single conception of happiness of patients are suspect because they are liable to
that could be used as a standard for the eval- biases of memory and to a process of evaluation
uation of institutions and public policy. The that sometimes violates elementary logical
extent of disagreement about the constitu- rules,” Kahneman writes.54 He is therefore
tion and measurement of happiness is best motivated to distinguish between the “remem-
grasped by looking at the views of a few bered utility,” the retrospective evaluation of an
prominent happiness scholars. episode, and the “total utility,” the aggregation
Let’s start with Richard Layard, who in his of “moment utilities” over a period of time.
book Happiness blithely merges all four According to Kahneman, “subjective happi-
notions into one (or jumps from one to anoth- ness” is (unreliably) “remembered utility,” and
er with abandon), assuming that well-being is “objective happiness” is the “total utility” over
no more or less than happiness, that happi- your life so far. “The implication of this analy-
ness is no more or less than a flow of pleasant sis,” Kahneman argues, “is that the goal of pol-
experience, and that life satisfaction surveys icy should be to increase measures of objective
reliably indicate the average hedonic quality of well-being, not measures of satisfaction or sub-
the stream of subjective states.50 Layard jective happiness.”55 Kahneman has therefore
proudly declares himself an unreconstructed developed the experience sampling and day-
disciple of British utilitarian philosopher reconstruction self-report methods in order to
Jeremy Bentham, who held that happiness or minimize the distortions of broad-brush self-
“utility” is no more or less than pleasurable report measures like happiness surveys.
experience, and that his Principle of Greatest So Richard Layard and Daniel Kahneman,
Happiness—that the right action or rule is perhaps the two most eminent proponents
always the one that will maximize happiness of a classically utilitarian, hedonistic concep-
so construed—is the one and only evaluative tion of happiness, disagree fundamentally
standard for both individual and political about the measurement techniques that best
decisionmaking. “I believe that Bentham’s provide information about happiness as they
idea was correct,” Layard confesses, “and that understand it. According to Layard, “It is the
we should fearlessly adopt it and apply it to long-term average happiness of each individ- The views of
our lives.”51 ual that this book is about, rather than the
Nobel Prize-winning Princeton psycholo- fluctuations from moment to moment,” yet prominent
gist Daniel Kahneman—a good bet as the his policy proposals lean heavily on precisely happiness
most influential living experimental cogni- the kind of life satisfaction survey data that
tive psychologist—also takes a page from Kahneman has proven to fail in extracting an
scholars fail
Bentham and conceives of happiness in line accurate average from the hedonic flow.56 spectacularly to
with idea (2), the quality of experience on a Is the unadorned hedonistic notion of converge on a
pleasure/pain or good/bad continuum.52 happiness and well-being advanced by
However, unlike Layard, Kahneman forceful- Layard and Kahneman as the basis of a “sci- single conception
ly denies that idea (1), judgments of life satis- ence” of happiness and well-being actually of happiness that
faction, reliably track the hedonic quality of true? That’s not a scientific question. It’s a could be used as a
experience over time. philosophical question about the nature of
In a famous 1996 study on the ability of moral value, and philosophical questions standard for the
patients to recall the painfulness of an unpleas- about moral value aren’t what economists evaluation of
ant medical procedure (a colonoscopy), Kahne- and psychologists are trained to answer.
man, together with medical researcher Donald Is happiness really nothing more than a
institutions and
Redelmeier, demonstrated that patient self- relatively high average quantity of pleasure public policy.

13
We don’t over one’s lifetime? As philosopher Robert “now considered so implausible that there is
necessarily value Nozick noted, a miserable life with a moment not a single living philosopher (to the best of
of transcendent bliss at the very last moment my knowledge) who is willing to defend it.”60
episodes with may have higher average hedonic utility than It’s not only moral philosophers who dis-
more total a normal life with normal satisfactions, but agree with Layard and Kahneman (who dis-
few of us would choose the former.57 agree with each other about what would
pleasure over Similarly, a life that starts out at a peak of count as evidence that someone is happy).
episodes with immense happiness but slowly erodes so that Other happiness researchers disagree with
less. each moment is slightly less pleasant than them, too, and with each other.
the last may contain a greater average of Julia Annas may be heartened to know
hedonic utility than a normal life, but, again, that a number of happiness researchers do
only a masochist would want it. It is plausible integrate Aristotelian, or eudaimonistic,
that many or most of us value the distribution ideas of happiness as objective flourishing
of pleasure over the course of life: we may into their studies. Martin Seligman, the
value a life that feels good generally and gets doyen of the “positive psychology” move-
better over time more than, say, a hugely ment, argues that the “measurable compo-
volatile life of towering peaks of pleasure and nents of what people mean by happiness”
deep pits of despair, even if the latter is more include pleasure, eudaimonia (which he
pleasurable on average. Which is just another characterizes as “engaged well-function”),
way of saying we don’t necessarily value and a sense of meaning in life.61 In Happiness:
episodes with more total pleasure over The Science Behind Your Smile, University of
episodes with less. Newcastle psychologist Daniel Nettle con-
We also have Nozick to thank for the ceives of “happiness” as a multivalent term
famous thought experiment of the “experi- encompassing three distinct “levels.” For
ence machine,” a device in which we live out Nettle, “Level One” happiness consists of
the rest of our lives in something like a coma, “momentary pleasures.” “Level Two” happi-
but with the vivid experience of the most ness consists of “judgments about feelings,”
pleasurable life we can possibly imagine.58 the same idea captured by “life satisfaction.”
Nozick argues that the fact so many of us Level Three” happiness is taken to concern
would choose a less pleasurable life with real “quality of life,” which Nettle sees as eudai-
engagement, real accomplishment, and real monistic “flourishing” or “fulfilling one’s
failure over an ideally blissful life of illusion potential”—a more objective notion of well-
plugged into the machine—even were we com- being.62 Carol Ryff identifies two traditions
pletely confident that it would work exactly as in well-being research, one focused on “hedo-
advertised—shows that pleasure cannot be nic well-being”—the SWB that dominates
the only thing we value. happiness research—and one focused on
“Time and philosophical fashion have not “eudaimonic well-being,” which she charac-
been kind to hedonism,” notes University of terizes as “perceived thriving vis-à-vis the exis-
Toronto philosopher Wayne Sumner, the tential challenges of life” and labels “psycho-
author of an influential treatise on well- logical well-being” or PWB.63
being. “Although hedonistic theories of vari- Seligman, Nettle, and Ryff’s complex con-
ous sorts flourished for three centuries or so ceptions of happiness and well-being are sim-
in the congenial empiricist habitat, they have ilar, attempting to frame a notion of happi-
all but disappeared from the scene. Do they ness richer than simple pleasure, but they
now merit even passing attention, for other also differ in important respects. In any case,
than nostalgic reasons?”59 University of it is apparent that most current techniques
Alabama economist and philosopher of sci- for measuring happiness—such as life satis-
ence Erik Angner observes that the hedonis- faction survey questions or experience sam-
tic conception of happiness and well-being is pling—capture only a small part (perhaps the

14
least profound part) of the larger idea of hap- dopamine—which is one important reason
piness or well-being each has in mind. While people choose to live in cities. So is it better, in
complex conceptions of well-being are more terms of good and bad feelings, to live in the
nuanced—and for that reason alone more country or the city? It depends on how much
plausible as accounts of a good human life— you value peace vs. stress, familiarity vs. novel-
than Layard or Kahneman’s hedonism, their ty. If there is no external standard for deter-
complexity also creates daunting problems mining the value of different dimensions of
of measurement. And even if any of them are affect, then there is no universally right
measurable, their complexity threatens to answer. Better for whom?
make them unfit as standards for the evalua- Whether it is better, in terms of feelings, to
tion of public policy. live in the city or the country may be no differ-
A study by Ryff and her coauthors com- ent than the question of whether it is better, in
paring measures of hedonic SWB with eudai- terms of feelings, to live in Sweden or the
monic PWB helps illustrate why. Ryff and her United States. Some Americans may feel better
team found that although SWB and PWB are in Sweden, and, judging from Minnesota, many
generally strongly correlated, they come Swedes may feel right at home in America.
apart for some people due to factors of indi- Philosopher Nicolas White argues that
vidual personality. “We found,” they wrote, people don’t want to be happy as much as to
The complex
“that those with high levels of psychological achieve their aims, whatever they may be. The biochemistry of
thriving (i.e., PWB) but low levels of happi- concept of happiness surely involves some good and bad
ness (i.e., SWB) were distinguished from their level of positive experience, but by and large it
opposite counterpart (high SWB/low PWB) is a blank that we fill in by the achievement of feelings suggests
by their levels of Openness to Experience.”64 our plans, projects, and goals. As we change that there are
The point here is that if there is more than our goals, balance conflicting desires, and
one dimension to happiness or well-being, amend and specify the details of our plans,
many more than
then there may be trade-offs between them, at our conceptions of happiness changes: two dimensions
least for some people. If life satisfaction and even to hedonic
positive affect aren’t all there is to happiness As we develop a picture of what life is to
or well-being, then the attempt to maximize be like, we don’t start from a “frame- well-being, and so
them may come at the expense of something work” concept of happiness (an idea of trade-offs among
else of value, such as a sense of challenged what the picture on the puzzle is to be), them are
thriving. And in that case, even a benevolent to which we tailor our particular aims
dictator endowed with perfect knowledge so that they’ll fit into it. . . . For the most inevitable.
would be unable to maximize all dimensions part, we build up a conception of what
at once. The dictator would have to make a happiness would be out of the aims that
value judgment about which dimension of we have. But we never have or try for a
happiness is most important. But even then: completely and consistently articulated con-
most important to whom? cept of happiness, or even suppose that
As I suggested in the previous section, the there must be such a thing. . . . If that’s
complex biochemistry of good and bad feel- right, then in an important sense the
ings suggests that there are many more than history of the concept of happiness has
two dimensions even to hedonic well-being, been a search for something that’s
and so trade-offs among them are inevitable. unobtainable.65
The noise, bustle, and danger of a big city are
no doubt a source of higher levels of cortisol And if that’s right, happiness is not mea-
and thus stress. Which is one important rea- surable, since there is no one thing indepen-
son some people would rather live in the coun- dent of individual aims “out there” to mea-
try. But cities can also be a greater source of sure. This is not to say that the various dimen-
stimulating novelty—more short bursts of sions of good and bad feeling are not each

15
measurable. Nor is this to say that a sense of Likewise, almost no one denies that hap-
challenged thriving, a sense of meaning, or the piness is important (not in Western societies
sense that life is satisfying is beyond the reach at least), even if some deny that it is most
of measurement and analysis. The point is important. And whatever different people
simply that different people with different think about how happiness is constituted,
aims may prioritize each of these things quite most of us would like more pleasure, more
differently and yet be equally concerned with “flow,” a greater sense of meaning, and a
their “happiness.” There is no order of such greater sense of self-efficacy in the face of
priorities that represents happiness par excel- life’s challenges. If a psychologist ambles up
lence, and an evaluative standard biased to you with a clipboard, and asks how happy
toward any one of them isn’t a standard com- you are with life as a whole, then, if you’re like
mitted to happiness per se. me, you would like to be able to sincerely say:
Moreover, there are plausibly nonsubjective “very happy.”
aspects of well-being, such as health, longevi- Despite the foregoing criticisms, happi-
ty, real opportunity, the development of basic ness research as it stands is far from useless.
human capacities, and the achievement of We can make the best use of it if we don’t
values other than happiness. Not only do naively assume that happiness is really the pri-
people give different weights to the various mary subject of measurement and research,
elements of happiness and well-being, people as if the elusive nature of happiness has been
don’t even agree about what they are. What’s pinned down at long last. Happiness research
more, many people don’t even agree that does tell us something about how we feel,
happiness or well-being, however conceived, is and it tells us a lot about the conditions
the greatest good. The fact of disagreement under which different kinds of people are
over the nature of happiness, or the nature of inclined to say that they are satisfied or
the good more generally, does not establish unsatisfied with life. Good feelings are
that there is no right answer to these ques- important, and so are culture-laden judg-
tions. The presence of disagreement among ments that life is going well, even if happiness
reasonable people is simply an empirical is more and less than that. It would be pretty
fact—what philosopher John Rawls calls “the incredible if the disposition to say that we are
fact of pluralism”—that places a hard con- happy on a survey didn’t correlate well with
straint on both the practical success and certain good feelings and other good things.
moral legitimacy of policies derived from any And the evidence is clear that it does.
evaluative standard.66 I have done my best to expose the weak-
Polities can manage the fact of pluralism by nesses of the dominant survey methods in
looking to general values common across oth- order to provide a much-needed counter-
erwise conflicting worldviews. “People can weight to the often complacent confidence in
agree, for example, on the importance of hav- their reliability and lack of care in the inter-
ing opportunities for self-expression (the exact pretation of their results. When intellectuals
form of these opportunities being as yet and politicians use putatively scientific data
unspecified) even though they disagree sharply for political purposes, it is important to apply
Many people over the merits of particular speeches, plays, careful scrutiny to their methods and to the
don’t even agree demonstrations, etc.,” notes Harvard political way their results are interpreted and used. If,
that happiness philosopher T. M. Scanlon. “Similarly, people however, we are very careful when comparing
who hold very different and conflicting beliefs happiness survey results across different cul-
or well-being, may still be able to agree that ‘being able to fol- tures or across long periods of time; or when
however conceived, low one’s religion’ is (for those who have one) looking at studies that make no note of indi-
an important part of life, and consequently a vidual personality differences, that do not fol-
is the greatest personal value that must be given significant low the same individuals over time, or that
good. weight in moral argument.”67 sample an exceptionally diverse population, it

16
is possible to glean solid information about example, Figure 1, which presents psychologist If we take the
things almost all of us care about that ought Adrian White’s “Map of World Happiness” data at face value,
to have real weight—if not all the weight—in based on the World Database of Happiness
our public deliberation about our political international rankings. the obvious
and economic institutions and policies. In The United States is evidently among the conclusion is that
that regard, it is heartening that recent studies world’s happiest nations, on par with Canada,
deploy more sophisticated research designs, Australia, New Zealand, Ireland, Norway,
the United States
better econometric techniques, better theoret- Sweden, Switzerland, and a few surprises, like is among the
ical constructs, larger data sets, and integra- El Salvador and Nigeria. Notably, the largest happiest places in
tion with more objective and rigorous biologi- European social democracies, Germany and
cal measurement techniques. France, fall one or two ranks below the United the world.
So let’s return to our main question: do States.
these studies show that the political and eco- In various rankings using different sur-
nomic institutions of the United States are fail- veys, the United States consistently ranks
ing its citizens in their pursuit of happiness? from the mid-teens to the mid-twenties out of
more than 200 countries—in or around the
90th percentile—in terms of average self-
Is There Something Wrong reported happiness. A 2005 Harris poll using
with the United States? the Eurobarometer questions found the
United States to be happier than every
Happiness research presently falls short as European country, other than Denmark. Or
good science and fails to get off the ground consider Table 1, which lists the top 50 coun-
as an adequate ethical standard for evaluat- tries in self-reported happiness according to
ing public policy. These conclusions admit- the World Values Survey. The United States
tedly follow from a fairly complex train of ranks higher than Sweden, Norway, Belgium,
reasoning starting from a number of con- Finland, Germany, and France. So much for
testable assumptions that are impossible to Benjamin Radcliff’s claim that “life satisfac-
vindicate fully in such a short space. Maybe tion should increase as we move from less to
you’re not entirely convinced. That’s okay. more social democratic welfare states.”68 If we
Even if you don’t buy the foregoing analy- take the data at face value, the obvious con-
sis of the complex methodological and philo- clusion is that the United States is among the
sophical problems that dog happiness happiest places in the world.
research; even if you remain convinced that As noted in my introduction, psychologist
recent survey-based scholarship really does Geoffrey Miller believes that “the utilitarian
give us highly reliable and useful information argument for the rich giving more of their
on the determinants of happiness and well- money to the poor is now scientifically
being; even if you think happiness so con- irrefutable.”69 Would Americans be happier
ceived really is the primary target at which with a larger and more generous welfare
policymakers ought to aim, it remains possi- state? If the argument for downward redistri-
ble to accept survey-based happiness research bution is “irrefutable,” then the evidence for
at face value and show that the U.S.-style it ought to shine forth in the data. According
socioeconomic model is not only a recipe for to Dutch sociologist Ruut Veenhoven, chief
immense riches, which no one disputes, but a of the World Database of Happiness and
winning recipe for happiness. founder and editor of the Journal of Happiness
A casual glance at the comparative interna- Studies, there is barely a flicker of a finding for
tional happiness data is enough to make us a welfare-happiness connection:
wary of the claim that there is some special
problem with the United States relative to other Contrary to expectation there appears
nations in terms of happiness. Consider, for to be no link between the size of the

17
Figure 1
A Global Projection of Subjective Well-Being

Source: Adrian G. White, “A Global Projection of Subjective Well-being: A Challenge to Positive Psychology?”
Department of Psychology, University of Leicester, http://www.le.ac.uk/pc/aw57/world/sample.html.

welfare state and the level of wellbeing redistribution does not have any significant
within it. In countries with generous effect on the subjective well-being of the unem-
social security schemes people are not ployed. The general picture is that they are nei-
healthier or happier than in equally ther happier nor healthier in welfare states.”71
affluent countries where the state is Ouweneel concludes that “in first world
less open-handed. Increases or reduc- nations there is no consistent pattern of social
tions in social security expenditure are security levels having a positive effect on well-
not related to a rise or fall in the level of being indicators.”72
health and happiness either.70 By contrast, Notre Dame political scientist
Benjamin Radcliff does finds a small statisti-
Another Dutch happiness researcher, Piet cally significant positive effect of generous wel-
Ouweneel of Erasmus University, Netherlands, fare spending on average happiness, and Har-
Greater welfare conjectured that at least the unemployed would vard economist Rafael Di Tella finds a small
spending had have higher average well-being, according to a boost from generous unemployment benefits.
no statistically number of indicators, in nations that spent a Ouweneel, however, criticizes both studies for
larger percentage of GDP on welfare. But comparing a very small set of countries.
significant greater welfare spending had no statistically sig- Further, he notes both were able to achieve sta-
effect—even on the nificant effect—even on the happiness of the unem- tistical significance only by treating successive
ployed. While larger welfare states generally do years in these countries as independent data
happiness of the achieve lower levels of income inequality points—a methodological faux pas.73
unemployed. through redistribution. “This apparent income The most conservative inference to draw

18
Table 1
Subjective Well-Being Rankings of 50 Countries

1. Puerto Rico 4.67 26. France 2.61


2. Mexico 4.32 27. Argentina 2.61
3. Denmark 4.24 28. Vietnam 2.59
4. Ireland 4.16 29. Chile 2.53
5. Iceland 4.15 30. Taiwan 2.25
6. Switzerland 4.00 31. Domin.Rep. 2.25
7. N. Ireland 3.97 32. Brazil 2.23
8. Netherlands 3.86 33. Spain 2.13
9. Canada 3.76 34. Israel 2.08
10. Austria 3.69 35. Italy 2.06
11. El Salvador 3.67 36. E. Germany 2.02
12. Venezuela 3.58 37. Slovenia 2.02
13. Luxembourg 3.52 38. Uruguay 2.02
14. United States 3.47 39. Portugal 1.99
15. Australia 3.46 40. Japan 1.96
16. New Zealand 3.39 41. Czech Rep 1.94
17. Sweden 3.36 42. South Africa 1.86
18. Nigeria 3.32 43. Croatia 1.55
19. Norway 3.25 44. Greece 1.45
20. Belgium 3.23 45. Peru 1.32
21. Finland 3.23 46. China 1.20
22. Saudi Arabia 3.01 47. South Korea 1.12
23. Singapore 3.00 48. Iran 0.93
24. Britain 2.92 49. Poland 0.84
25. W. Germany 2.67 49. Turkey 0.84

Source: Based on Ronald Inglehart, “Subjective Well-Being Rankings of 82 Societies,” World Values Survey.
http://www.worldvaluessurvey.org/Upload/5_wellbeingrankings.doc Latin American countries, which score high-
er than predicted given the quality of their economic and political institutions, are in italics. The wealthy OECD
countries are in bold. Ex-communist countries are underlined. East and West Germany are scored separately to
reflect the effects of their different institutional histories.

from the existing happiness literature is that itive effect on happiness, aside from progres-
if the redistributive openhandedness of the sive redistribution, is that a higher rate of gov-
state has any effect on happiness at all, it is a ernment spending as a percentage of GDP
surpassingly small one. When slightly differ- might indicate better provision of the kinds of
ent econometric techniques using slightly public goods that unaided market institutions
Economists
different datasets generate weak correlations are often thought to be incapable of provid- Christian
in opposite directions, the correct lesson to ing.74 But economists Christian Bjornskov, Bjornskov, Axel
draw is that the variable barely matters at all. Axel Dreher, and Justina Fischer find that “life
If Americans are less happy on average than satisfaction decreases with higher government Dreher, and
citizens of some other nations—and we are spending.”75 Intriguingly, they also find that Justina Fischer
happier than all but a handful—the scope the “negative impact of the government is find that “life
and generosity of the welfare state has little stronger in countries with a leftwing median
or nothing to do with it. voter”—which is to say, in places where voters satisfaction
If relatively lavish welfare spending fails to most want big government. decreases with
increase happiness, other forms of govern- Advocates of progressive taxation and
ment spending might nevertheless succeed. income redistribution through welfare trans-
higher govern-
One reason big government could have a pos- fer payments often attempt to justify those ment spending.”

19
Alberto Alesina, policies not only in terms of the increased course, it is possible to criticize Americans for
Rafael Di Tella, well-being of the least well-off, but in terms having unrealistic beliefs about mobility, for
of the overall importance of reducing income they are generally unrealistic, especially among
and Robert inequality generally. In theory, high relative the poor. But if inequality has no negative
MacCulloch have income and social status are important to effect on happiness independent of attitudes
happiness, and we are therefore aggravated toward mobility, it seems that a happiness-
found that by the conspicuous display of goods we can- promoting policymaker would want to
inequality in the not afford. If true, it would make sense for a encourage, not discourage, the American con-
United States has leveling of incomes to have some positive viction in mobility.
effect on happiness. But, again, empirical evi- By most measures, income inequality has
no effect on the dence is hard to come by. been rising in the United States. However,
self-reported Alberto Alesina, Rafael Di Tella, and Robert inequality in happiness has declined. Rising
happiness of the MacCulloch have found that inequality in the income inequality, then, does not imply a
United States has no effect on the self-reported widening gap in satisfaction with life. On the
poor. happiness of the poor. “Probably the most contrary, Americans are becoming more equal
striking result of all is the complete lack of any in happiness even as the income gap widens.
effect of inequality on the happiness of the Sociologist Jan Ott finds that rising average
American poor and the American left,” they levels of happiness go together with decreas-
report. There is a very small statistically signif- ing levels of happiness inequality because the
icantly negative effect in the United States, but “level and equality of happiness depend even-
it is driven almost entirely by the effect of tually on the same institutional conditions.”
inequality on the rich. This is so striking in part And the institutions of wealth creation are
because it is basically the reverse of the situa- among the most important: “Wealth con-
tion in Europe, where there is a much larger tributes to higher levels of happiness and cre-
negative effect of inequality, due mostly to the ates ample possibilities to reduce inequality in
dislike of inequality by the poor and left-wing happiness,” Ott writes.77
voters.76 The creation of wealth depends on a com-
This contrast between Europe and the plex system of underlying economic, legal, and
United States raises a crucial point about the cultural institutions. Other things equal,
interpretation of the effect of macroeconomic nations that ensure their citizens’ greater eco-
variables on happiness—namely, their effect is nomic freedom are also wealthier. The United
culturally and ideologically mediated. The States is the most visible embodiment of the
authors argue that the different effects of ideals of economic freedom on the world
inequality in Europe and the United States are stage. However, emphasis on the importance
due largely to different prevailing attitudes of distinctively economic freedom in the happi-
about income mobility. Whether or not their ness literature is relatively new, which is per-
beliefs are realistic, Americans—even the poor haps one reason the ideals of relatively
and the left-wingers—have a strong faith in the unhampered markets and open exchange—
possibility of upward mobility, at least com- ideals strongly associated with the United
pared to Europeans. Under those conditions, States on the world stage—have yet to get ade-
the fabulously rich demonstrate to other quate emphasis in popular accounts of happi-
Americans just how astronomically high it is ness research.
possible to rise and stand out as figures of Ott finds that economic freedom as mea-
admiration and emulation. (This is perhaps sured by both the Heritage Foundation and
why rich-bashing populism is a perpetual elec- the Fraser Institute correlates strongly with
toral failure in U.S. politics.) The American high and highly equal levels of happiness—as
rich also believe strongly in mobility, but strongly as almost any variable.78 Veenhoven
where there are wide income disparities, they finds that economic freedom correlates more
see all too clearly how far they could fall. Of strongly with happy-life-years (HLY) than any

20
Figure 2
Self-Reported Happiness and Economic Freedom

Source: Tomi Ovaska and Ryo Takashima, “Economic Policy and the Level of Self-Perceived Well-Being: An
International Comparison,” Journal of Socio-Economics 35 (2006): 314.

variable other than wealth (as measured by is well placed. Based on the regression
purchasing power per capita) and degree of results, economic freedom holds some
social tolerance (i.e., acceptance of plural- promise in serving as one of the policy
ism).79 And in the largest study on economic tools that could be potentially used to
freedom and happiness yet conducted, econo- increase the SWB of a nation’s popula-
mists Tomi Ovaska and Ryo Takashima find tion.80
that economic freedom is the variable most
highly correlated with self-reported happiness According to Ovaska and Takashima, “The
(see Figure 2). According to Ovaska and results suggest that people unmistakably
Takashima: care about the degree to which the society Economic free-
where they live provides them opportunities
Compared to the GDP per capita mea- and the freedom to undertake new projects,
dom correlates
sure, the index of economic freedom— and make choices based on one’s personal strongly with
personal choice, freedom to compete preferences.”81 high and highly
and the security of privately owned According to the Heritage Foundation’s
property as its core components— 2007 Index of Economic Freedom, the United equal levels of
turned out to be about four times as States ranked fourth, behind Hong Kong, happiness—as
important, as measured by elasticities. Singapore, and Australia. And according to strongly as
This indicates that the newly found the Fraser Institute-Cato Institute 2006
interest of economics and of policymak- Economic Freedom of the World Report, the almost any
ers in measures of institutional quality United States was in a three-way tie for third variable.

21
There is almost with Australia and Switzerland, behind Hong ture of American misery, nor does it even hint
no evidence in the Kong and Singapore. The evidence is extreme- at a problem with America’s conduciveness to
ly strong that the outstanding level of eco- happiness relative to the European social
happiness nomic freedom in the United States has a democracies.
literature to strong effect on its high showing in the inter-
national happiness comparisons. Any policy
support the idea package aiming to improve American happi- Taxing Ambition
that Americans ness should have initiatives to improve eco-
would be better nomic freedom at the forefront. As noted at the outset, some of the most
A fair look at a number of the most recent, compelling happiness-based arguments for
off with either and most sophisticated, happiness studies income redistribution are built on the alleged
lower levels of suggests that the United States, far from being importance of relative as opposed to absolute
income inequality a problem country, exemplifies many of the income and wealth. However, these arguments
institutional virtues that strongly predict high are much more theory-driven than data-dri-
or a policy of levels of national self-reported happiness. ven, turning on a very particular hypothesis
more generous Although the United States is routinely criti- about the role and importance of social status
cized by Europeans and its own political left in human life. We have already seen that the
welfare transfers. for a stingy welfare state and high levels of empirical happiness-based case for reducing
income inequality, there is almost no evidence in inequality and increasing welfare spending is
the happiness literature to support the idea extraordinarily weak. It should not be surpris-
that Americans would be better off with either ing, then, that a hypothesis about human
lower levels of income inequality or a policy of nature that leads to poor predictions about
more generous welfare transfers. The high lev- inequality and redistribution should also be
els of economic growth and economic free- ill-supported by the facts. However, because
dom in the United States are effectively the relative position hypothesis is so com-
increasing the average American level of hap- pelling to some very fine minds, it is impor-
piness while decreasing inequality in life satis- tant to understand in detail why it fails and
faction between its citizens. why the importance of relative position pro-
If we take the current international com- vides no credible happiness-based case for
parisons at face value, one very clear picture more redistribution.82
emerges: advanced, liberal-democratic market The politics of relative position encourages
economies are the happiest places on Earth. us to see life as a competitive climb up a ladder
However, if we descend from such rarefied of status. If there can be only one person per
heights of generality, the picture goes blurry. rung on any dimension of status or rank, then
The data are too coarse to distinguish among each step up the ladder for one person logical-
packages of specific policies—to tell us, for ly requires a step down for another. You can’t
example, that we would be happier with make space for an eleventh restaurant or uni-
mandatory paid maternity leave, or with versity on a “Top Ten” list, just as two runners
greater restrictions on the content of advertis- can’t both come in first. Competition for
ing to children. As with inequality, we will higher position is a paradigmatic zero-sum
often find that the effect of policy on happi- game—every move up is offset by a corre-
ness is mediated by culturally specific beliefs sponding move down. So if inherently scarce
and attitudes. So, beyond a general recom- positional goods like ladder rank are highly
mendation to increase economic freedom and valued, then whenever you get a raise, a pro-
eliminate policies that hinder economic motion, or a swank new suit, you must create
growth (which I will discuss in detail below), a shower of negative psychic consequences
there is almost no specific guidance here for a that rain on those occupying the rungs below.
policymaker. The picture that does emerge According to Layard, Frank and others, we
from the data is most emphatically not a pic- fiercely value inherently scarce positional

22
goods because we fiercely value status—the impossible for individuals to negotiate a
ultimate positional good. This explains, they truce, so a trusted third party—the state—
posit, why average self-reported happiness has must step in and impose a price cap or a tax
not gone up over time, though wealthier peo- on fancy suits (or cars, houses, or whatever)
ple at any time are more likely to be happier. in order to mitigate the “harm” caused by
Higher relative standing makes us happier, but self-defeating attempts to get ahead.
the middle of the income distribution is the The intractability of zero-sum positional
middle, no matter how big the number. So competition for Frank and Layard flows from
there is no avoiding the positional downside of a rather nasty conception of human nature,
every positional upside. But, they insist, we can- according to which we are dominated by a uni-
not simply shrug off the inevitable cruelty of a versal, inflexible, deep-seated, status-seeking
world in which our interests are in irreconcil- instinct, together with a remarkably narrow,
able conflict. Policy must take human nature materialistic conception of how positional
seriously and do what it can to help. We should competition is culturally mediated. Theirs is a
take the dismay and anxiety caused by zero- distressingly agonistic vision of the human
sum competition over positional goods just as predicament in which life is irremediably
seriously as sludge dumped in a stream, the brutish and nasty, if not short. “The desire for
roar of jets at a nearby airport, or other classic status is utterly natural,” Layard writes. “But it
The intractability
examples of negative spillover effects (or “nega- creates a massive problem if we want to make of zero-sum
tive externalities”) of economic activity. people happier, for the total amount of status positional
In addition to the “harms” caused by any is fixed . . . If my score improves, someone else’s
upward positional move, Frank and Layard deteriorates.”84 competition for
worry about the negative effects of positional In our original evolutionary context, Frank Frank and Layard
“arms races.” If I try hard to move up the argues, higher-rank individuals would have
positional ladder, the people just ahead will had greater access to material resources and
flows from a
try harder still to maintain their lead. In the the highest quality mates, increasing the pro- rather nasty
end, we’re all likely to wind up about where portion of their genes in future populations. conception of
we started in terms of relative position, but Therefore, Frank concludes, “it would be
we’ll all be exhausted by the race. As an illus- strange indeed if the relentless forces of natur- human nature.
tration, Frank highlights the signaling func- al selection had not honed a human brain that
tion of fashion: strongly motivated its bearer to seek high
rank.”85 Mother Nature has doomed us, like
If some job candidates begin wearing other primates, to act as status-seeking mis-
expensive custom-tailored suits, a side siles.
effect of their action is that other candi- Layard recognizes this line of thought may
dates become less likely to make favor- sound ugly to certain ears. Accordingly, he
able impressions on interviewers. From imagines a critical “libertarian” who objects
any individual job seeker’s point of view, that public policy based on our status-fixation
the best response might be to match the affirms and rewards an “ignoble sentiment
higher expenditures of others, lest her [like envy] that ought to be disregarded.” He
chances of landing the job fall. But this responds:
outcome may be inefficient, since when
all spend more, each candidate’s proba- This is an extraordinarily weak argu-
bility of success remains unchanged. All ment. Public policy has to deal with
may agree that some form of collective human nature as it is. The desire for sta-
restraint on expenditure would be use- tus is after all ubiquitous, and we all rec-
ful.83 ognize it. Greed is also common, and
libertarians do not disallow it. Both sen-
Frank argues that it is often impractical or timents are features of human nature.

23
We are not perfect, and public policy statements that all primates know domi-
should help us make the best of what we nance-subordination relationships,” writes
are.86 Frans de Waal, the world’s leading expert on
primate hierarchies.92
Layard is concerned to get us to take the Real and profound differences are also
inescapability of status-racing seriously, or glossed over by failing to acknowledge what is
else his argument for taxes on positional peculiar to humans. For one thing, we are
“pollution” will fall apart. He’s right that we uniquely cultural creatures, and this funda-
must deliberate about policy “taking men as mentally transforms the zero-sum logic of the
they are and laws as they might be,” as primate dominance hierarchy. We have
Rousseau put it.87 And we should not be sur- already seen how the effects of macroeconom-
prised to find that our theory of human ic phenomena like inequality are mediated by
nature will largely determine which laws and culture-bound belief systems. Even universal
institutions seem feasible and desirable. human psychological traits are highly mediat-
However, although Frank and Layard’s forays ed by diverse human cultural formations. Like
into speculative evolutionary psychology monkeys and chimps, we all eat. But some eat
may be better than “extraordinarily weak,” with fingers, some with forks, and some with
they don’t amount to a state-of-the art con- a tuxedoed waiter and violins. There is no
ception of human nature “as it is,” either. denying that all humans signal status, but the
Taking people as they really are is the down- differences between a silk necktie and a bound
fall of the politics of relative position. foot are not morally trivial. A high-status
It is true that status is no ideological drug-dealing gangster and a high-status barn-
fancy; it has a real organic basis. Frank and raising Amish family man may each be “alpha
Layard both refer to studies involving vervet males” within their groups, but the social con-
monkeys showing that serotonin and testos- sequences of positional competition for vio-
terone concentrations correlate positively lent power and for upstanding modest piety
with position in the deference-dominance are hardly the same.
hierarchy.88 Similarly, in an article in the New Indeed, a sensible measure of a culture’s
Yorker on the importance of relative (as quality is the extent to which it can shape
opposed to absolute) poverty, writer John potentially destructive natural propensities,
Cassidy notes that low-ranking baboons have such as self-interest, status seeking, tribal sol-
elevated levels of stress hormones, and that idarity, and mate competition, into benign or
low-ranking rhesus monkeys face elevated even beneficial cultural forms.93 Although
A sensible risk of arteriosclerosis.89 There is some good our taste for status may be deep, the fact that
measure of a evidence of similar physical correlates of sta- our cultural capacity mediates our instincts,
tus in humans. “If monkeys enjoy status, so causing the form and value of their expres-
culture’s quality do human beings,” Layard reasons.90 He then sion to vary wildly, prevents facile extrapola-
is the extent to rushes to explore the policy implications of tion from tendency to policy.
intractable status competition. This turn toward culture is far from a soft-
which it can But the fact that we are not actually vervet headed evasion of hard biological truths.
shape potentially monkeys or baboons matters a great deal. Cultural flexibility is our biological nature.
destructive Species differences matter a lot, even between Recent work by Peter Richerson, Robert Boyd,
monkeys and chimps. Pioneering primatolo- Joseph Henrich (a zoologist and two anthro-
natural gist and psychologist Abraham Maslow first pologists), and others point out the adaptive
propensities into pointed out the vast difference in behavior advantages of a labile cultural capacity that
benign or even between often friendly and tolerant domi- allows human populations to adapt quickly to
nant chimpanzees and vigilantly despotic changing environments and accumulate and
beneficial cultural dominant rhesus monkeys.91 “Real and pro- transmit useful knowledge, norms, and insti-
forms. found differences are glossed over by flat tutions across generations.94 In a paper on the

24
cultural evolution of cooperation, Boyd, ning nemesis, but this triviality will be There is no
Richerson, and Henrich point out that the swamped by the benefits that flow to people reason why
common human cultural capacity explains the who may not even know the innovator’s name.
huge variation in cooperative institutions and The logic is basically David Hume’s in his dimensions of
norms between societies. Whether we happen essay “The Rise and Progress of the Arts and status cannot be
to be locked in zero-sum or positive-sum Sciences,” where he attributes the advance of
games is more a matter of culturally transmit- knowledge and beauty precisely to a combina-
multiplied
ted institutions (norms of interaction and tion of “emulation,” the ambition to equal or indefinitely.
coordination, explicit or tacit) than of brute surpass others (positional competitiveness),
facts about our genetic constitution.95 The and a taste for “praise and glory” (freely con-
question, then, isn’t whether we are status ferred prestige).97 Hume may well have had
seeking. The question is how our culture and himself in mind when he observed, “A writer is
institutions harness, suppress, or amplify our animated with new force, when he hears the
natural tendencies. applauses of the world for his former produc-
Henrich, with anthropologist and psy- tions; and, being roused by such a motive, he
chologist Francisco Gil-White, has argued often reaches a pitch of perfection, which is
that the distinctive human cultural capacity equally surprising to himself and to his read-
creates space for kinds of status based in the ers.”98 The world is better, not worse, for
positive-sum trade of specialized knowledge Hume’s own avidly status-seeking “love of lit-
and expertise for “prestige.” They argue that erary fame,” his confessed “ruling passion.”99
freely conferred prestige provides both an We applaud for a reason: to stimulate the sup-
incentive to develop excellence in a valued ply of excellence by gratifying the demand for
domain and a payment for the demonstra- status.
tion and transmission of scarce knowledge Crucially, there is no limit to the possible
and skills that benefit members of the group: forms of excellence. So, although the number
of positions on any single dimension of sta-
In humans, in contrast [to other pri- tus may be fixed, there is no reason why
mates], status and its perquisites often dimensions of status cannot be multiplied
come from non-agonistic sources—in indefinitely. It does not in fact require a vio-
particular, from excellence in valued lation of mathematical law to produce more
domains of activity, even without any high-status positions, for it is possible to pro-
credible claim to superior force. For duce new status dimensions.
example, paraplegic physicist Stephen In his fascinating analysis of the economics
Hawking . . . certainly enjoys high status of fame, economist Tyler Cowen interprets
throughout the world. Those who, like praise as the currency with which fans reward
Hawking, achieve status by excelling in and manipulate fame-seeking performers, and
valued domains are often said to have concludes, in an argument addressed to Frank,
“prestige.”96 that fame-seeking is a positive-sum, not a neg-
ative-sum, game. “Given the benefits of trading
It cannot be denied that prestige based in praise for performance, markets continually
superior knowledge of theoretical physics is find new means of accommodating and
light-years from that enjoyed by a dominant attracting fame-seeking,” Cowen writes.100 And
vervet monkey tyrannizing its cowering markets continually find new means of accom-
underlings. Henrich and Gil-White’s concep- modating and attracting more garden-variety
tion of nonagonistic prestige based in valued forms of status-seeking as well.
excellence points to the exit from Layard and New dimensions of excellence and status
Frank’s grim, zero-sum world. To be sure, the often open up as a result of technological
runner-up in the race to cure a disease may be innovation. It was impossible to be a chart-
infuriated by the prestige granted to his win- topping pop star or a champion triathalete

25
before there were radios and bikes. Liberal neurs receive enormous prestige and status
market societies not only create new technolo- precisely in order to encourage scientific and
gies, they create proliferating forms of associa- startup activities,” they write.102 The benefits
tion, affiliation, expression, and identity at a of such status seeking, they say, may more
sometimes alarming rate.101 Each musical than offset the negative effect of status “arms
genre, hobby, committee, church, club, ideolo- races.” Even if the taste for relative position is
gy, and lifestyle provides a new dimension—a unavoidable, Indiana University economist
new frame of reference—for positional compe- Richmond Harbaugh argues that fear of
tition. Environmental purists can compete falling behind can induce high rates of sav-
with one another to conspicuously consume ings—a kind of stockpiling for future status-
eco-friendly products (or conspicuously refuse signaling consumption races—with positive
to consume much at all), while punk rockers overall effects on economic growth.103 So,
duke it out on grounds of anti-establishment there may well be negative external effects of
authenticity and economics professors knock positional competition, but when we add the
themselves silly trying to get articles into eso- positive effects, the net externality may turn
teric journals no one else cares about. out to be positive. We can draw no sound
The cultural fragmentation some critics implication for policy by blinding ourselves to
The cultural frag- lament is precisely what liberates us from one column of the cost-benefit ledger.
mentation some unavoidable zero-sum positional conflict. If some positional competition creates neg-
critics lament is Surfer dudes don’t compete with Star Trek ative spillovers, the best policy solution is less
geeks for status. Dynamic market liberal soci- clear than Frank, Layard, and others imply. In
precisely what eties create higher-order positive-sum games his seminal 1960 article, “The Problem of
liberates us from (for example, the “create a new status dimen- Social Cost,” Ronald Coase destroyed the
sion” game, or the “find the status dimension older conception of externalities.104 Coase
unavoidable zero- on which you rank highest” game) that have drew attention to the fact that externalities
sum positional lower-order zero-sum games as parts. exist only as an interaction of preferences. I may
conflict. Once we recognize the anarchic multidi- smell of jasmine, to the delight of most who
mensionality of status, the frequent supposi- enter my orbit. But if you are allergic, my fra-
tion of Frank, Layard, Cassidy, and others grance may be far from pleasant. A tax on jas-
that the distribution of income—whether within mine may benefit you, but at the cost of those
the office or within the nation—is the main who take pleasure in the scent. Coase instructs
dimension of positional competition begins us to look for the “least-cost avoider.” If it
to look ridiculous. Struggling artists do not costs you least simply to stay out of wafting
necessarily doubt their superiority in the face distance, then that will be the most efficient
of successful accountants. And it should not course.
need pointing out that many of us simply The cultural variability and open-ended-
don’t know how much our friends make and ness of status make it clear that we are not
don’t much care. helpless to avoid the harsh side-effects of
Are the external effects of positional com- positional competition. If it is within our
petition really like pollution, as Layard says? power to opt out of any particular status race
Or is positional competition more like the and to compete for status on a different
light of the sun: it can burn you, but nothing dimension, those “harmed” may well be the
grows without it? Nobel Prize winner Gary least-cost avoiders. Remember Frank’s exam-
Becker and his University of Chicago col- ple of competing job applicants in a race to
league, Clark Medal winner Kevin Murphy, buy an ever-fancier suit? The fact is, you sim-
have argued that without the motivating ply don’t have to apply for that job. And even
prospect of increased status, there would be if you really want to, you can always buy your
“underinvestment” in entrepreneurial activity: suit on the cheap from Overstock.com, hope
“Great scientists and outstanding entrepre- nobody notices, and use the $500 you saved

26
to buy studio time for your new indie-emo- we ought to stick it to the rich, but to get a
folk band—that is, to compete on another better grasp on how rich we all really are.
dimension of status. Indeed, if we extrapolate from Hagerty, the
More importantly, as Michael Hagerty’s happiness-based policy implication of his
study discussed above makes clear, although a study is that we should once again revise the
plurality of people taking a happiness survey Consumer Price Index so that it stops under-
do determine their answer on the basis of estimating growth in real wages.106 We’d be
some kind of concurrent social comparison, happier if government statistics didn’t con-
people are easily able to shift their frame of ref- ceal how much better off we really are.
erence and respond to the survey on the basis Work by psychologist Bram Buunk shows
of intertemporal personal comparison, or that individuals can differ strongly in what
intertemporal social comparison, in which he calls “social comparison orientation” or
case their self-reported life satisfaction increas- SCO. It turns out that it is not good for you
es. All it takes is for the experimenter to ask to be high in SCO:
them to look at things a different way. If the
“negative externality” vanishes simply because Individuals high in social comparison
people have shifted the perspective from orientation are characterized by a sense
which they answer a happiness survey ques- of uncertainty about themselves as well
tion, then the idea that there are real “harms” as by a strong concern with their own
here, or that the state might have an interest in motives and feelings, as apparent from
preventing them, becomes hard to swallow. substantial correlations of social com-
The “harm” appears to be a phantom of an parison orientation with neuroticism,
easily ameliorable bias toward concurrent and with public and private self-con-
social comparison in survey respondents. It’s sciousness. Moreover, and particularly
hard not to be amused by the “policy implica- relevant here, individuals high in social
tion” Hagerty draws from his study: comparison orientation are relatively
low in intellectual autonomy (one of
The intertemporal questions above the Big Five dimensions) and tend to
show . . . that people are quite willing to have a strong interest in how others are
change their standard of comparison doing in order to evaluate their own
(at least temporarily). National happi- characteristics.107
ness may therefore be increased by
encouraging people to compare them- It is well-known that neuroticism in par-
If the “negative
selves with their own grandparents, who ticular correlates negatively with self-report- externality”
had far worse health, education, social ed happiness, while intellectual autonomy vanishes simply
mobility, and job benefits than today, (also known as “openness to experience”) cor-
and who hoped for better lives for their relates positively with Ryff’s “challenged because people
children. The present study shows that thriving.”108 People high in SCO feel worse have shifted the
people currently compare themselves when others are doing better, while people
far less to their own past (as little as low in SCO simply don’t notice. It seems
perspective
11%) than to current standards such as unwise to create policy that would symboli- from which they
social comparisons or current aspira- cally endorse and possibly reinforce what answer a happi-
tions. Therefore, encouraging people to appears to be a psychologically problematic
compare themselves with their own past orientation. And it seems deeply unfair to ness survey
(rather than with current others or cur- raise taxes on everyone simply on the basis of question, the idea
rent aspirations) would increase judg- the fact that some people can’t help compar- that there are real
ments of happiness.105 ing themselves to others. Happily, Buunk
and coauthors show that people high in SCO “harms” becomes
The policy implication is not so much that aren’t stuck feeling sour about others’ rela- hard to swallow.

27
Even those of us tive success: they can be taught to pay more happier, and no one on average gets ahead
most inclined attention to those doing worse, with divi- anyhow, then what’s the point of everybody
dends in self-reported happiness. Even those getting richer? What’s the point of a high rate
to compare of us most inclined to compare ourselves to of GDP growth? We could grind away a lot
ourselves to others can reduce the “harms” of relative less, be a bit less rich, but also a bit happier.
position simply by choosing to pay attention We should relax more instead: build model
others can reduce to something else. airplanes, spend time with the kids, adopt a
the “harms” of Frank, acknowledging the logic of Coase’s highway, or whatever—and policy should
relative position least-cost avoider principle, argues that even help make this easier. Money isn’t everything,
people who are uninterested in status may be and there’s something wrong with a govern-
simply by harmed anyway by others’ positional competi- ment that doesn’t seem to understand that.
choosing to pay tion. For example, “positional externalities in “GDP is a hopeless measure of welfare,”
attention to the housing market,” Frank argues, “also Layard concludes. “For since the [Second
entail far more tangible costs, most notably World] War that measure has shot up by
something else. that failure to keep up with community leaps and bounds, while the happiness of the
spending patterns means having to send one’s population has stagnated.”110 Elsewhere he
children to schools of below average quality. writes, “We desperately need to replace GDP,
The scope for accommodation to such costs however adjusted, by more subtle measures
seems far more limited” than in cases where of national wellbeing.”111 This also is the
we can simply choose not to let relative posi- kind of thinking that led Andrew Oswald to
tion bother us or volitionally to switch our write, “Economists’ faith in the value of
frame of social comparison.109 But this, growth is diminishing. That is a good thing
Frank’s best example of a case where it is hard and will slowly make its way down into the
to opt out, is in fact a strikingly poor example. minds of tomorrow’s politicians.”
It turns entirely on the irrational bundling of It has, in fact, made its way to the minds of
schools and neighborhoods in the American today’s politicians. As British prime ministerial
public school system, a problem that could be hopeful David Cameron announced last
entirely alleviated with school choice policies spring, “It’s time we admitted that there’s
that would allow families to send their kids to more to life than money, and it’s time we
fancy schools outside their own modest neigh- focused not just on GDP, but on GWB—
borhood. This suggests that the most direct General Wellbeing.” In Cameron’s plea one
policy implications of positional competition can hear echoes of Robert Kennedy’s famous
may not be higher taxes on work and con- attack on national income accounts as a mea-
sumption, but policies, like school choice, that sure of human well-being. Stumping for pres-
make it easier to pick and choose among races. ident just months before his tragic murder,
It should be possible to give your kids a leg up Kennedy lamented that a measure like GDP
in the education race without living in an
expensive neighborhood. Frank identifies a does not allow for the health of our
cost of the status quo system of education children, the quality of their education,
financing, not a cost of positional competi- or the joy of their play. It does not
tion in general. include the beauty of our poetry or the
strength of our marriages; the intelli-
gence of our public debate or the
Getting Rich, Getting Happy integrity of our public officials. It mea-
sures neither our wit nor our courage;
The relative position hypothesis also helps neither our wisdom nor our learning;
drive the animus toward economic growth. If neither our compassion nor our devo-
we’re grinding away to get ahead, and every- tion to our country; it measures every-
body gets richer, but money doesn’t make us thing, in short, except that which

28
makes life worthwhile. And it tells us ed with GDP per capita,” either positively or
everything about America except why negatively.115
we are proud that we are Americans.112 In his recent book, The Moral Consequences of
Economic Growth, Harvard economist Benjamin
Kennedy was right that national income Friedman emphasizes that in addition to the
statistics don’t tell us much about “our wit” or litany of its astonishing humanitarian benefits,
“the joy of our children’s play.” Nevertheless, if economic growth is also a powerful force for
we’re looking for a single socioeconomic vari- the encouragement of broadly liberal social
able that tracks with most objective indicators and political aims. “The value of a rising stan-
of well-being, GDP per capita is hard to beat. dard of living lies not just in the concrete
Even if it does not measure everything that improvements it brings to how individuals
makes life worthwhile (because nothing does), live,” Friedman writes, “but in how it shapes
it most definitely relates positively to mea- the social, political, and ultimately moral char-
sures of a lot of good things, including happi- acter of a people. Economic growth—meaning
ness. But before looking at the effects of a rising standard of living for the clear majori-
money on happiness, I will examine how ty of citizens—more often than not fosters
important high average individual wealth, as greater opportunity, tolerance of diversity,
measured by GDP per capita, can be to non- social mobility, commitment to fairness, and
Economic
subjective indicators of well-being. dedication to democracy.”116 growth is a
A large recent study by OECD economists And as Tyler Cowen has detailed at powerful force
Romina Boarini, Asa Johansson, and Marco length, wealthier societies produce more
Mira d’Ecole focused on the relationship paintings, poems, films, songs, operas, and for the encour-
between GDP per capita and alternative mea- sculptures. They build more museums, sup- agement of
sures of well-being in the OECD nations. The port more symphonies, and patronize more
authors found significant positive correla- artists than do less wealthy societies. Econ-
broadly liberal
tions of GDP per capita with self-sufficiency, omists can’t tell a skeptic about economic social and
average years of schooling, life expectancy at growth whether the poetry is beautiful, but at political aims.
birth, healthy life expectancy at birth, mortali- least there is more of it, and most of us,
ty risks, and volunteering. Further, GDP per economists or not, recognize that much of it
capita was significantly negatively correlated is in fact beautiful.117
with income inequality, relative poverty, child So economic growth makes us healthier,
poverty, and child mortality.113 As economists better educated, and more public spirited;
Vito Tanzi and Hamid R. Davoodi show, GDP fosters social toleration; increases the integri-
per capita is also significantly positively corre- ty of our public institutions; and produces a
lated with lower levels of corruption—so GDP surfeit of art and culture. But does economic
may have something to say about the “integri- growth make us happier?
ty of our public officials” after all.114 It is impossible to review the happiness lit-
Given the serious charge that high-growth erature without constantly tripping over the
market societies erode “social capital” and fact that GDP per capita, or some other proxy
fray the social fabric, it is important to note for average wealth, dominates almost all vari-
that even if GDP per capita is not significant- ables in terms of the strength of correlation
ly positively associated with most indicators with a society’s average happiness. As we have
of social cohesion other than rates of volun- already seen, at any time and place, individuals
teerism and a decrease in crime, neither does with higher relative income are more likely to
it appear to accompany symptoms of social say they are “very happy.” But, as we are con-
breakdown. According the authors, “indica- stantly reminded, the idea that average happi-
tors of crime victimization, prisoners and ness has not increased with average income is
suicides—as well as of divorces, drug use and a bedrock finding of happiness research. It is
road accidents—are not significantly correlat- also false.

29
Figure 3
Life Satisfaction and GDP per capita

Source: Tomi Ovaska and Ryo Takashima, “Economic Policy and the Level of Self-Perceived Well-Being: An
International Comparison,” Journal of Socio-Economics 35 (2006).

On average, wealthier nations have happi- They argue that the data are inconsistent
er people, as Figure 3 makes clear. Moreover, with the predictions of strong relative posi-
the most recent statistical work on the rela- tion theories and that although adaptation
tionship between wealth and happiness, does reduce the rate of increase in happiness,
using larger sets of data and more sophisti- it does not wash out all absolute gains in
cated techniques of analysis, show unequivo- happiness from increasing wealth.118 There
cally that we are getting happier as we get are non-relative and non-evaporating gains
richer. from wealth. They conclude:
In a recent debate with Richard Easterlin
in the journal Social Indicators Research, Happiness is apparently not a zero-sum
Michael Hagerty and Ruut Veenhoven have game and can be raised by growth in
argued that increasing wealth is making us national income. This has been a central
happier. Much of the debate centers on small but until recently untested belief of
esoteric points of statistical methodology economists and public policy analysts.
and how to rhetorically frame the conclu- Not too long ago unhappiness was
sions. However, Veenhoven and Hagerty’s deemed the normal human condition.
There are non- methods do appear to be a marked improve- Since expulsion from Paradise, humans
ment over most past happiness studies, and could only hope for happiness in the
relative and non- their well-argued interpretation of their find- after-life. Promises of greater happiness
evaporating gains ings goes mostly unchallenged by Easterlin, in earthly existence were dismissed as
from wealth. which augurs ill for the anti-growth crowd. overly simplified utopianism. The cur-

30
Figure 4
Happiness Adjusted Life-Years in the United States 1948–1998

Source: Ruut Veenhoven, “Apparent Quality-of-Life In Nations: How Long and Happy People Live,” Social
Indicators Research 71 (2005): 61–86.

rent research on happiness allows empir- of the 20th century. If a longer happy life is If a longer happy
ical tests of this, and has shown that happier than a shorter happy life, then life is
entire nations can become happier with evidently getting happier with growth (see life is happier
economic growth and its covariates.119 Figure 4). than a shorter
The exact effect of rising wealth on the happy life, then
Happiness researchers have mostly told us trend of rising HLY is difficult to tease out, as
about average self-reported happiness at a GDP per capita tends to correlate with so life is evidently
particular time and over time. But we have many other positive indicators. Veenhoven getting happier
been told little about how long a representa- shows that the gains in HLY do diminish
tive person in a society can expect to live at rapidly (but never to zero) above about
with growth.
the average level of happiness. For example, $15,000 of average income (see Figure 5).
most cross-national comparative studies However, the returns to HLY from economic
can’t see the difference between two equally and political freedom do not appear to be
happy societies, one of which has an average diminishing, and these are the variables that
lifespan of 30 years and the other of which tend to predict growth.
has an average of 80. But if we’re making As Veenhoven shows in Table 2, purchas-
judgments on the standard of happiness ing power per head is the strongest single
alone, a society in which you can expect an determinant of HLY. The fact that correla-
extra 50 years of happiness has got to be bet- tions for all other indicators (with the excep-
ter. Veenhoven’s HLY measure takes longevi- tion of “trust in compatriots”) weaken after
ty into account. His method is to take a controlling for wealth suggests that wealth
nation’s life-expectancy at birth and multiply and growth explain, at least in part, the levels
it by average happiness converted to a scale of other positive social conditions, such as
from 0 to 1 (e.g., a 5 on a 10-point happiness freedom, tolerance, civil rights, lower levels of
scale becomes .5, etc.). When we switch to the corruption, discrimination against women,
HLY indicator for the United States, we see and inequality in happiness—strongly sup-
HLY levels clearly rising during the last half porting Benjamin Friedman’s argument for

31
Figure 5
Wealth and Happy Life-Years in 66 Countries in the 1990s

Source: Ruut Veenhoven, “Apparent Quality-of-Life In Nations: How Long and Happy People Live,” Social
Indicators Research 71 (2005): 61–86.

the broadly liberalizing effects of economic crisis in the mid 1990s, which severely disor-
growth.120 ganized the economy. As the Russian econo-
The best studies are those that track peo- my began to pick up, so happiness also began
ple over time and see what happens to their to rise.”122
happiness as their circumstances change. One Despite the apparently overwhelming evi-
such study used the reunification of East and dence that wealthy, high-growth societies are
West Germany—and rapidly rising incomes in the happiest places in the world, and only get-
the East—as a kind of natural experiment to ting happier, there is no lack of hand-wringing
test whether increasing incomes do make us about the spiritual emptiness of “materialism”
happier. In a paper titled “Money Does in liberal market societies, and some of the
Matter!” the authors write: hand-wringing is motivated by putatively sci-
entific findings. In his 2004 book The High
average life satisfaction in East Price of Materialism, Knox College psychologist
Germany increased by around 20% Tim Kasser presents his research with Richard
between 1991 and 2001, leading to a Ryan showing that “extrinsically motivated”
clear convergence with West Germany. people who care predominantly about materi-
Importantly, increased real household al acquisition are more likely to find them-
incomes in East Germany accounted selves unhappy and dissatisfied with life than
Sudden for around 35–40% of this increase, are “intrinsically motivated” people devoted to
reductions in which corresponds to the economists’ personally meaningful work and relation-
income correlate view that money surely matters.121 ships. Kasser’s research on the negative effects
of “materialistic” value orientation on happi-
strongly with On the flip-side, sudden reductions in ness seems sound and conforms to common
declining income correlate strongly with declining sub- sense.
jective well-being. Hagerty and Veenhoven However, Kasser barely takes a breath
subjective note that “in Russia average happiness before taking an awesome leap in logic from
well-being. decreased by two points following the Rubel the micro to the macro level of diagnosis.

32
Table 2
Social Conditions and Happy-Life-Years in 67 Countries in the 1990s

Correlation with HLY


Condition in Nation Zero-order Wealth Controlled N

Wealth
Purchasing power per head* +0.73 66
Freedom
Economic* +0.71 +0.38 64
Political* +0.53 +0.13 63
Personal –0.61 +0.31 45
Equality
Disparity in incomes* –0.10 +0.37 62
Discrimination of women –0.46 –0.12 51
Disparity in happiness –0.64 –0.37 54
Brotherhood
Tolerance +0.72 +0.43 55
Trust in compatriots +0.20 +0.20 37
Voluntary work +0.40 +0.31 53
Social security +0.34 –0.27 34
Justice
Rule of law* +0.65 +0.20 64
Respect of civil rights* +0.60 +0.20 60
Corruption –0.73 –0.32 40
Explained variance by variables
marked with* 66% 60

Source: Ruut Veenhoven, “Apparent Quality-of-Life In Nations: How Long and Happy People Live,” Social
Indicators Research 71 (2005): 61–86.

Because extrinsically motivated individuals Showing that there is a problem with materi-
with predominantly materialistic values are alistic monomania says nothing about capital-
more likely to be unhappy, market societies, ist societies, nor does it imply that denizens of
which create unparalleled opportunities for capitalism are more likely to be materialistic
material accumulation and consumption and than others. Showing that
which motivate the production of goods and Recent studies by Stephanie M. Bryant,
services others value extrinsically with profits Dan Stone, and Benson Weir have developed there is a
and paychecks, must be unhappy.123 But this a new theoretical construct called Financial problem with
is a simple non sequitur. Kasser boldly equivo- Self-Efficacy, which they define as “the belief
cates on the meaning of the word “materialis- that one can competently manage one’s
materialistic
tic,” implying that consumer demand for finances.”124 The authors find that individu- monomania does
material consumption requires a widespread als high in FSE are more likely to treat money not imply that
“materialistic” attitude in his special theoreti- as an instrument for the achievement of other,
cal sense. However, capitalist consumer soci- nonmaterialistic aims. People high in FSE denizens of
eties—and markets in general—don’t require tend to have higher levels of debt but more capitalism are
materialistic monomania in order to operate. intrinsic motivation for carrying it (e.g., a stu- more likely to be
They require only that people want things, for dent loan, a family home, a trip to a foreign
good reasons or bad, and that they are willing country, etc.), and they are more likely to materialistic than
to trade what they have produced to get them. have high levels of life satisfaction. The others.

33
If you want fewer upshot is clear: the aspiration to make and have developed more sophisticated
materialists, make spend money is neither good nor bad. What forms of consumerism, materialism,
matters is our attitude toward our financial and hedonism. . . . New forms of con-
more material goals, and their content. If we want money sumption no longer function primari-
readily available simply for its own sake, to impress friends, or ly to indicate people’s economic class.
to buy gadgets as palliatives for boredom and Increasingly, they are means of individ-
to people, at ennui—Kasser’s “materialism”—money won’t ual self-expression.128
which point do us good. But if we regard money as a mere
they’ll stop worry- tool with which to achieve more meaningful Inglehart is not using “materialist” in pre-
ends, more money will help us do more of cisely the same way as Kasser, but the rough
ing about it so what we find meaningful. idea—an emphasis on material acquisition as
much and start University of Michigan political scientist opposed to meaning—is the same. If you
worrying instead Ronald Inglehart’s work shows that nations want fewer materialists, the way to go is to
with a rising level of per-capita GDP tend to shift make more material readily available to peo-
about things like culturally from “materialist” values, “which ple, at which point they’ll stop worrying
happiness and the emphasize economic and physical security,” to about it so much and start worrying instead
“post-materialist” values, “which emphasize self- about things like happiness and the meaning
meaning of life. expression and quality of life.”125 According to of life.
Inglehart, the cultural shift includes a signifi- Many people seem to think that a govern-
cant time lag, because “to a large extent, one’s ment’s emphasis on measurements like GDP
basic values reflect the conditions that prevailed indicate a kind of collective affirmation of
during one’s pre-adult years.”126 Inglehart finds materialist goals, encouraging a narrowly
that there has been a large shift from materialist materialist attitude at war with more exalted
to post-materialist values in wealthy Western lib- values. But this is simply a mistake. The very
eral market democracies. function of money is to serve as a neutral
medium of exchange. It is a shape-shifting
For example, in the earliest U.S. survey, embodiment of almost any value. The same
materialists outnumbered postmateri- $100 can be spent on a prostitute or donated
alists by 24 percentage points; in West to an HIV/AIDS clinic. The relative value
Germany, they outnumbered postma- neutrality of money is precisely why the mea-
terialists by 34 points. During the three surement of per-capita wealth is well suited
decades following 1970, a major shift to pluralistic liberal societies; it doesn’t beg
occurred: by the 1999–2001 surveys, many questions about competing concep-
postmaterialists had become more tions of the good life. Money can’t be con-
numerous than materialists in all nine verted into anything that someone might
countries.127 value, but it is of the nature of money to be
convertible into a phenomenally broad range
This, of course does not mean that of values. Societies with high levels of average
younger generations spend all their time income and wealth are societies in which peo-
shopping for “fair trade” coffee and perform- ple have more resources at their disposal to
ing sun salutations (though there is surely achieve their aims, no matter what those
more of that). But the shift away from eco- aims might be, which is why it should be no
nomic scarcity increases the emphasis on self- surprise that, other things equal, people with
definitional and self-expressive consumption. more money are more satisfied. By measur-
“The rise of postmaterialism does not mean ing GDP, household wealth, and the like,
that materialistic issues vanish,” Inglehart government is not affirming one set of values
and Christian Welzel write: over others. It is, in fact, embodying an ideal
of liberal neutrality by measuring something
The publics in postindustrial societies that is valuable in varying degrees to all of us.

34
ity, with a heretofore unthinkable indepen-
Conclusion dence from custom, wondering what kind of
person we would like to be. And then we
The United States is not failing the become agoraphobic.
Founders’ test. The happiness-based evidence Our problem is that there are both too
points unambiguously to the conclusion that many and too few choices. There are particu-
those of us lucky enough to live in the United lar goods that would specially benefit and
States in 2007 are succeeding fairly well in the satisfy each of us, but which don’t exist. Yet it
pursuit of happiness. Whether or not our is hard to identify the specially fitting goods
Founders would recognize—or even like—their that already do exist in the panoply of choice.
country, Americans are indeed living up to the If we weren’t so diverse, we wouldn’t require
promise of our founding. so much diversity. One kind of shoe, one
So, we are left with a puzzle. If we’re so kind of bread, one kind of antacid would be
happy, then why are we so ready to be per- universally satisfactory. But we are diverse,
suaded by claims that we are suffering from a and, for the first time in history, we are liber-
world-historical spiritual malaise, despite all ated from ancient demands of conformity,
the evidence to the contrary? because, for the first time in history, we now
In his bestselling 2004 book The Paradox of come into the world at a sufficiently safe dis-
In fine post-
Choice, Schwartz argues that capitalist con- tance from scarcity to permit us to express materialist
sumer culture gets us down by offering too and experiment with our singular natures. In fashion, we
many choices. It’s not just that the onslaught fine post-materialist fashion, we demand
of new brands of toothpaste, breakfast cereal, that our consumption express our self-con- demand that our
chocolate bars, and books about happiness ceptions-in-progress, and so we need diversity. consumption
taxes our frail deliberative capacities, but when But we also don’t know exactly who we want
our set of options explodes, each new choice to be before we get to the store. So we can eas-
express our
requires not choosing so many other things.129 ily feel lost in the consumer cornucopia, as self-conceptions-
The perceived cost of making any choice and though we are sorting through a landfill for in-progress, and
sticking with it seems higher and higher the a diamond etched with just our name.
more alternatives there are to forgo. On this As John Maynard Keynes wrote in his star- so we need
score, Schwartz points us to Robert Lane’s tlingly prescient essay “Economic Possibilities diversity.
claim in The Loss of Happiness in Market for Our Grandchildren,” there may be a sense
Democracies: in which we have already solved (we lucky few
in the advanced liberal democracies, that is)
There are too many life choices . . . the economic problem of scarcity. But then
without concern for the resulting over- what?
load; and the lack of constraint by cus-
tom, [and] demands for self-actualiza- Thus for the first time since his creation
tion, that is, demands to discover or man will be faced with his real, his per-
create rather than accept a given iden- manent problem, how to use his free-
tity . . . all adds to the stress.”130 dom from pressing economic cares,
how to occupy the leisure, which science
To be sure, it is a hassle to have to discover and compound interest will have won
or create our identities instead of being for him, to live wisely and agreeably and
“given” one—or having one forced upon us. well.131
But this is, in essence, what it means to be
postmaterialist in Inglehart’s sense. Instead of And this, our permanent problem, we have yet
slipping into pre-assigned, traditional social to solve, and it weighs on us. Our culture has
roles, we are able to sit atop mountains of not yet caught up to the new, happier world of
wealth and survey the vast horizon of possibil- science and compound interest, and we do not

35
yet see how our inherited visions of the good Notre Dame ReSource, August 24, 2006, http://
newsinfo.nd.edu/content.cfm?topicid=18802.
life fit into it. So it seems plausible to most of
us that something is wrong, even if so much is 11. Miller.
right. If happiness research is going to be good
for anything, it is not going to be for guiding 12. Barry Schwartz, “Choice Cuts,” New Republic
Online, August 5, 2004, http://www.tnr.com/doc
well-meaning technocrats who seek to make print.mhtml?i=express&s=schwartz080504.
us happier by pulling this policy lever or push-
ing that policy button. Rather it is going to be 13. Jon Gertner, “The Futile Pursuit of Happiness,”
good for providing insight in how “to live New York Times Magazine, September 7, 2003, p. 44.
wisely and agreeably and well.” This is insight 14. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, p. 152.
we all badly need, and it is not the govern-
ment’s to give. 15. Andrew Oswald, “The Hippies Were Right All
Along about Happiness,” Financial Times, January
18, 2006.

Notes 16. The survey, results, and analysis of many dif-


ferent studies can be found at http://worldvalues
1. Richard Layard, Happiness: Lessons from a New survey.org.
Science (New York: Penguin, 2005), p. 3.
17. The text of the Midlife Development Inventory
2. David G. Myers, The American Paradox: Spiritual can be found at http://www.midus.wisc.edu/mid
Hunger in an Age of Plenty (New Haven, CN: Yale us1/mail_parts_1_2.pdf .
University Press, 2001), pp. 1, 7–8.
18. See Ed Diener et al., “The Satisfaction with
3. Gregg Easterbrook, The Progress Paradox: How Life Scale,” Journal of Personality Assessment 49, no.1
Life Gets Better While People Feel Worse (New York: (1985). The scale itself can be found at http://
Random House, 2003), p. xx. www.psych.uiuc.edu/~ediener/hottopic/hottop
ic.html.
4. Ibid., p. xvii. Easterbrook here is quoting Alan
Wolfe’s formulation of Robert Lane’s thesis in 19. See Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi and Jeremy
Wolfe’s review essay “Undialectical Materialism,” Hunter, “Happiness in Everyday Life: The Uses of
The New Republic, October 23, 2000, pp. 28–43. Experience Sampling,” Journal of Happiness Studies
4, no. 2: 185–99; and Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi,
5. Richard A. Easterlin, “Does Economic Growth Flow: The Psychology of Optimal Experience (New
Improve the Human Lot?” in Nations and House- York: Harper and Row, 1990).
holds in Economic Growth: Essays in Honor of Moses
Abramovitz, ed. Paul A. David and Melvin W. 20. Daniel Kahneman et al., “A Survey Method for
Reder (New York: Academic Press, 1974). Characterizing Daily Life Experience: The Day
Reconstruction Method,” Science 3, no. 570
6. Geoffrey Miller, “Social Policy Implications of the (December 2004): 306.
New Happiness Research,” an answer to Edge.org’s
question “What Is Today’s Most Unreported Story,” 21. See Carol D. Ryff et al., “Positive Health:
www.edge.org/3rd_culture/story/86.html. Connecting Well-Being with Biology,” Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London 359 (2004):
7. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, pp. 233–34, for 1383–94; and Heather L. Urry et al., “Making a Life
Layard’s policy laundry list. On education, see also, Worth Living: Neural Correlates of Well-Being,”
pp. 200–201. Psychological Science 15, no. 6 (2004).
8. Randolph M. Nesse, “Natural Selection and the 22. For a recent overview, see Ed Diener, Richard
Elusiveness of Happiness,” Philosophical Transactions E. Lucas, and Christie Napa Scollon, “Beyond the
of the Royal Society of London B, (2004): 1335. Hedonic Treadmill: Revising the Adaptation
Theory of Well-Being,” American Psychologist 61,
9. Benjamin Radcliff, “Politics, Markets, and Life no. 4 (May-June 2006): 205–314.
Satisfaction: The Political Economy of Human
Happiness,” American Political Science Review 95, 23. Easterlin defends his aspiration theory against
no. 4 (December 2001): 941. the adaptation-set point theory in Richard A.
Easterlin, “A Puzzle for Adaptive Theory,” Journal
10. Quoted in Susan Guibert, “Liberal Policies of Economic Behavior and Organization 56, no. 4
Equal Happier Citizens, Says Political Scientist,” (2004): 513–21.

36
24. Robert Frank, Luxury Fever (Princeton: Princeton “Measurement Issues in Emotion Research,” in Well-
University Press, 1999), is devoted to exploring the Being: The Foundations of Hedonic Psychology, ed.
implications of the relative position hypothesis. Kahneman, Diener, and Schwarz (New York: Russell
Sage Foundation, 1999), pp. 48–49. They continue,
25. On the cultural relativity of smiling, see Anna “[A] person might “have” an emotion in a nonverbal
Wierzbicka, “‘Happiness’ in Cross-Linguistic and channel (for example, autonomic activation or
Cross-Cultural Perspective,” Daedelus: Journal of the action tendency) yet never label that experience and
American Academy of Arts and Sciences 133, no. 2 hence not perceive it as an emotion at all.”
(Spring 2006): 36. On the socially “strategic” use
of “authentic” or “Duchenne” smiles, see Paul 41. Martin Seligman, Authentic Happiness: Using the
Griffiths and Andrea Scarantino, “Emotions in New Positive Psychology to Realize Your Potential for
the Wild: The Situated Perspective on Emotion,” Lasting Fulfillment (New York: Free Press, 2002), p.
in Cambridge Handbook Of Situated Cognition, ed. 105.
Philip Robbins and Murat Aydede (New York:
Cambridge University Press, forthcoming). 42. Shaun Frederick and George Loewenstein,
“Hedonic Adaptation,” in Kahneman, Diener, and
26. For example, Daniel Gilbert, Stumbling on Schwarz.
Happiness (New York: Knopf, 2006), pp. 67–70.
43. Mark Twain, “Captain Stormfield’s Visit to
27. Wierzbicka, p. 36. Heaven,” in Tales of Wonder, ed. David Ketterer
(Lincoln, NE: University of Nebraska Press, 2003),
28. Ibid., p. 37. p. 32.

29. Ibid., p. 43. 44. For an amazing account of improvement in the


objective quality of human life in terms of disease,
30. Ed Diener and Shigehiro Oishi, “Are Scandin- malnutrition, body size, and longevity, see Nobel
avians Happier than Asians? Issues in Comparing Prize–winning economist Robert William Fogel’s
Nations on Subjective Well-Being,” in Politics and The Escape from Hunger and Premature Death, 1700-
Economics of Asia, ed. F. Columbus (Hauppauge, NY: 2100: Europe, America, and the Third World (New
Nova Science, 2006). York: Cambridge University Press, 2004.)
31. Ibid. 45. Haybron, “Do We Know How Happy We Are?”
Haybron uses the example of the noisy office to
32. Andrew Clark et al., “Heterogeneity in Reported suggest that we are worse off than happiness sur-
Well-Being: Evidence from Twelve European veys indicate; modern life is like working in a
Countries,” The Economic Journal 115, no. 502 (2005). noisy office. No doubt stress levels have gone up
for people living in certain kinds of cities, or in
33. Gilbert, p. 69. certain kinds of jobs, but taking all the improve-
ments in medicine, technology and comfort into
34. Ibid, pp. 69–70. account, it is extremely implausible that we actu-
ally do feel worse overall than in the past.
35. Clark et al.
46. Gary Becker and Luis Rayo, “Evolutionary
36. Ibid. Efficiency and Happiness,” unpublished manu-
script, home.uchicago.edu/~gbecker/RayoBecker
37. Dan Haybron, “Happiness and the Importance LSE1.pdf
of Life Satisfaction,” unpublished manuscript,
2001, www.slu.edu/colleges/AS/philos/Happiness 47. Jeff T. Larsen, A. Peter McGraw, and John T.
AndTheImp.pdf. Cacioppo, “Can People Feel Happy and Sad at the
Same Time?” Journal of Personality and Social
38. Michael R. Hagerty, “Was Life Better in the Psychology 81, no. 4 (October 2001).
‘Good Old Days’? Intertemporal Judgments of Life
Satisfaction,” Journal of Happiness Studies 4, no. 2 48. Haybron, “Do We Know How Happy We Are?”
(June 2003).
49. Julia Annas, “Happiness as Achievement,”
39. Dan Haybron, “Do We Know How Happy We Daedalus 133 no. 2 (Spring 2004): p. 44.
Are? On Some Limits of Affective Introspection
and Recall,” Nous, forthcoming, http://pages.slu. 50. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, pp. 111–47.
edu/faculty/haybrond/DoWeKnowHowHappyW
eAre%20v61single.pdf. 51. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, p. 112.
40. Randy J. Larsen and Barbara L. Frederickson, 52. Daniel Kahneman, “Objective Happiness,” in

37
Kahneman, Diener, and Schwarz, pp. 4–5. (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2006), p. 173.

53. Donald Redelmeier and Daniel Kahneman, 66. On the fact of pluralism, see John Rawls,
“Patients’ Memories of Painful Medical Treatments: Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University
Real-time and Retrospective Evaluations of Two Press, 1993), p. 36.
Minimally Invasive Procedures,” Pain 116, pp. 3–8.
Redelmeier and Kahneman show that retrospective 67. T. M. Scanlon, The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays
judgments tend to track the average of the level of in Political Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
pain at its most intense and the level of pain at the University Press, 2003), p. 184.
end of the procedure. So a short procedure that ends
abruptly after its worst moment is remembered as 68. Radcliff, p. 941.
more painful than a longer procedure with an equal-
ly painful peak and a longer denouement to a less 69. Miller deploys an updated version of the classic
painful conclusion. The upshot is thus that an argument for redistribution from the diminishing
episode with more aggregate pain “in” it may be marginal utility of income. Political philosopher
remembered as less painful than an episode with and economist David Schmidtz notes that, even
“objectively” less pain “in” it, which means that we are granting utilitarian premises, diminishing margin-
often unreliable narrators of our hedonic histories. al utility need not have redistributive implications
in a world where not all income is immediately
54. Kahneman, “Objective Happiness,” p. 4. consumed, but in which some is invested in wealth-
creating production—that is, in the actual world.
55. Ibid., p. 15. David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 144–46.
56. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, p. 112.
70. Ruut Veenhoven, “Wellbeing in the Welfare
57. Robert Nozick, The Examined Life: Philosophical State,” Journal of Happiness Studies (2000).
Meditations (New York: Simon and Schuster,
1989), pp. 100–102. 71. Piet Ouweneel, “Social Security and Well-
Being of the Unemployed in 42 Nations,” Journal
58. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New of Happiness Research 3 (2002): 167–92, 2002.
York: Basic Books, 1976), pp. 42–45.
72. Ibid.
59. L. W. Sumner, Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), p. 83 73. Ibid. The number of nations in Radcliff is 11
and in Di Tella is 12. Ouweneel’s study looks at
60. Erik Angner, “Is it Possible to Measure Happi- 42.
ness? The Measurement-Theoretic Argument
against Subjective Measures of Wellbeing,” unpub- 74. See, for example, Charles B. Blankart and
lished manuscript, www.dpo.uab.edu/~angner/ Christian Kirchner, “The Deadlock of the EU
pdf/WelfareMeasurement.pdf. Budget: An Economic Analysis of Ways In and Ways
Out,” Center for Economic Studies and Ifo Institute
61. Martin Seligman, interview with John Brock- for Economic Research at the University of Munich,
man, “Eudaimonia, the Good Life: A Talk with CESifo Working Paper No. 989, 2003; Robert A.
Martin Seligman,” Edge: The Third Culture, http:// Musgrave, “The Theory of Public Finance: a Study in
www.edge.org/3rd_culture/seligman04/seligman Political Economy,” (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959);
_index.html. Arthur C. Pigou, “The Economics of Welfare” (New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2002).
62. Daniel Nettle, Happiness: The Science Behind
Your Smile (New York: Oxford University Press, 75. Christian Bjornskov, Axel Dreher, and Justina
2005), p. 18. Fischer, “The Bigger the Better? Evidence of the
Effect of Government Size on Life Satisfaction
63. Corey L. M. Keyes, Dov Shmotkin, and Carol D. Around the World,” Working Paper 05/44, Swiss
Ryff, “Optimizing Well-Being: The Empirical Federal Institute of Technology, Zurich, October
Encounter of Two Traditions,” Journal of Personality 2005. Emphasis added.
and Social Psychology 82, no. 6 (2002).
76. Alberto Alesina, Rafael Di Tella, Robert
64. Ibid. Openness to experience is one of the “Big MacCulloch, “Inequality and Happiness: Are Euro-
Five” personality traits—along with neuroticism, peans and Americans Different?” Journal of Public
extraversion, conscientiousness, and agreeable- Economics 88 (2004): pp. 2009–42.
ness—studied by personality psychologists.
77. Jan Ott, “Level and Inequality of Happiness in
65. Nicholas White, A Brief History of Happiness Nations: Does Greater Happiness of a Greater

38
Number Imply Greater Inequality in Happiness,” Henrich, “Cultural Evolution of Human Cooper-
Journal of Happiness Studies 6 (2005): 397–420. ation,” in The Genetic and Cultural Evolution of
Cooperation, ed. Peter Hammerstein, pp. 357–88.
78. Ibid.
96. Joseph Henrich and Francisco Gil-White, “The
79. Ruut Veenhoven, “Apparent Quality-of-Life In Evolution of Prestige: Freely Conferred Status as a
Nations: How Long and Happy People Live, Social Mechanism for Enhancing the Benefits of Cultural
Indicators Research 71 (2005): 61–86. Transmission,” Evolution and Human Behavior 22
(2001):1–32.
80. Tomi Ovaska and Ryo Takashima, “Economic
Policy and the Level of Self-Perceived Well-Being: 97. David Hume, “The Rise and Progress of the
An International Comparison,” Journal of Socio- Arts and Sciences,” Essays, Moral, Political, and
Economics 35 (2006): 308–25. Literary (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1987).

81. Ibid. 98. See Ibid.

82. Much of this section borrows from Will 99. David Hume, “My Own Life,” in The History of
Wilkinson, “Out of Position: Against the Politics England from the Invasion of Julius Caesar to the
of Relative Standing,” Policy (Spring 2006), Revolution in 1688, vol. 1 (Indianapolis: Liberty Fund,
http://www.cis.org.au/POLICY/spring_06/pol 1993).
spring06_wilkinson.htm.
100. Tyler Cowen, What Price Fame? (Cambridge,
83. Robert Frank, “Are Positional Externalities MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 102.
Different from Other Externalities?” Paper present-
ed at “Why Inequality Matters: Lessons for Policy 101. See Tyler Cowen, In Praise of Commercial
from the Economics of Happiness,” Brookings Culture (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Institution Conference, htp://www.brookings.edu/ Press, 1997) for an account of the success of mar-
gs/events/externalities.pdf, p 1. ket societies in producing, assimilating, and syn-
thesizing new forms of culture.
84. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, p 150. Emphasis added.
102. Gary S. Becker and Kevin M. Murphy, Social
85. Frank, Luxury Fever, p. 133. Economics: Market Behavior in a Social Environment
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 124.
86. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, p. 153.
103. Richmond Harbaugh, “Falling Behind the
87. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract, Joneses: Relative Consumption and the Growth-
Book 1, Paragraph 1. Savings Paradox,” Economics Letters 53 (1996):
297–304.
88. Frank, Luxury Fever, pp. 140–2.
104. Ronald Coase, “The Problem of Social Cost,”
89. John Cassidy, “Relatively Deprived,” The New Journal of Law and Economics 3 no. 1 (1960): 1–44.
Yorker, April 4, 2006.
105. Michael R. Hagerty, “Was Life Better in the
90. Layard, Happiness: Lessons, p. 150. ‘Good Old Days’? Intertemporal Judgments of
Life Satisfaction,” Journal of Happiness Studies 4, no.
91. See Frans de Waal, Good Natured: The Origins of 2 (June 2003).
Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals
(Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. 126. 106. Robert J. Gordon, “The Boskin Commission
Report and Its Aftermath,” NBER Working Papers
92. Ibid., pp. 126–27. 7759 (2000), http://www.nber.org/papers/w7759.
pdf. The Consumer Price Index estimates the rate of
93. Will Wilkinson, “Capitalism and Human inflation by identifying a “basket” of consumer
Nature,” Cato Policy Report, January/February 2005, goods and then comparing changes in the prices of
http://www.cato.org/research/articles/wilkinson- the items in the basket periodically over time. In
050201.html brief, the argument of the Boskin commission and
a majority of economists is that the CPI overesti-
94. See Robert Boyd and Peter J. Richerson, Not By mates the rate of inflation, and thus underesti-
Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human mates growth in real wages, by failing to capture
Evolution (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, quality changes in goods, failing to track the move-
2004) for an excellent overview of this work. ments of many consumers to lower-cost retailers
(e.g., “big box” stores or discount internet sites), and
95. Peter J. Richerson, Robert Boyd, and Joseph especially by failing to include the introduction and

39
rapid price declines of new technologies, some of of relative utility, happiness is not a zero sum game.
which are life-saving, and could not be purchased in Instead, increasing the income of all does increase
earlier periods at any price. the happiness of all, but adaptation reduces the
rate of increase to about half of its peak.” p. 21
107. Bram P. Buunk, Frans L. Oldersma, and Carsten
K.W. de Breu, “Enhancing Satisfaction through 119. Ruut Veenhoven and Michael Hagerty, “Rising
Downward Comparison: The Role of Relational Happiness in Nations 1946–2004: A Reply to Easter-
Discontent and Individual Differences in Social lin,” Social Indicators Research (2006) 79, pp. 421–36.
Comparison Orientation,” Journal of Experimental
Social Psychology 37 (2001): 452–67. 120. And, again, to the horror of egalitarian redistrib-
utionists, we find that higher levels of income inequal-
108. Kristina M. DeNeve, “Happy as an Extraverted ity correlate positively with happy-life-years, and high-
Clam? The Role of Personality for Subjective Well- er levels of welfare spending (“social security” on
Being,” Current Directions in Psychological Science 8, no. Veenhoven’s table) correlate negatively with happy-
5:141–44; and Keyes, Shmotkin, and Ryff. life-years when adjusted for wealth. The inequality
result is partly due to the fact that Latin American
109. Robert Frank, “Are Positional Externalities countries tend to have high levels of income inequal-
Different from Other Externalities?” p. 24. ity and also report unusually high levels of happiness.
Another part of the explanation, though, lies in the
110. Richard Layard, “Happiness: Has Social Science fact that societies can induce growth in part by allow-
Got a Clue?” London School of Economics, Lionel ing entrepreneurs to keep much of the profits from
Robbins Memorial Lectures, 2002/2003, http://cep. economic gambles, a tiny few of which pay off mas-
lse.ac.uk/events/lectures/layard/RL030303.pdf. sively, producing astronomical levels of income in the
top percentiles of the distribution.
111. Richard Layard, “Happiness is Back,” Prospect,
March 2005. 121. Paul Frijters, John P. Haisken-DeNew and
Michael A. Shields, “Money Does Matter! Evidence
112. Robert Kennedy, Address, University of Kansas, from Increasing Real Incomes and Life Satisfaction
Lawrence, Kansas, March 18, 1968. Kennedy in East Germany Following Reunification,” Ameri-
referred specifically to GNP, which has been largely can Economic Review 94, no. 3 (June 2004).
replaced by GDP for purposes of estimating the size
of the economy and rate of economic growth. GNP 122. Veenhoven and Hagerty, p. 433. See Ruut
apparently also tells the Bhutanese everything about Veenhoven, “Trend Average Happiness in Nations:
Bhutan except why they are proud to be Bhutanese, 1946–2004,” Trendreport 2005–1d, World Database
which is why King Druk Gyalpo Jigme Singye of Happiness, 2005, www.worlddatabaseofhappi
Wangchuck officially jettisoned GNP way back in ness.eur.nl/trendnat (+ year).
1974 in favor of what he calls “Gross National
Happiness.” See “Preface” in Gross National Happiness 123. Tim Kasser, The High Price of Materialism
and Development (Thimpu: Centre for Bhutan (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002), p. 106.
Studies, 2004), http://www.bhutanstudies.org.bt
/publications/gnh-dvlpmnt/GNH-I-1.pdf. 124. Stephanie M. Bryant, Dan Stone, and Benson
Wier, “Articulating a Positive Relationship to Money,”
113. Romina Boarini, Asa Johansson, and Marco presented at the Designing Information and Organi-
Mira d’Ercole “Alternative Measures of Well-Being,” zations with a Positive Lens Conference, November
OECD Social, Employment and Migration Work- 11–12, 2005, http://weatherhead.case.edu/design/
ing Papers, no. 33, February, 17, 2006, http://www. PositionPapers/Dan%20Stone%20et %20al.doc.
oecd.org/dataoecd/13/38/36165332.pdf
125. Ronald Inglehart and Christian Welzel, Mod-
114. Vito Tanzi and Hamid R. Davoodi, “Corruption, ernization, Cultural Change, and Democracy: The Human
Growth, and Public Finances,” IMF Working Paper Development Sequence (New York: Cambridge Uni-
WP/00/182, 2000. versity Press, 2005), p. 97.

115. Ibid. 126. Ibid., p. 98.

116. Benjamin M. Friedman, The Moral Consequences 127. Ibid., p. 103.


of Economic Growth (New York: Knopf, 2005), p. 4.
128. Ibid., p. 104.
117. Tyler Cowen, In Praise of Commercial Culture.
129. Barry Schwartz, The Paradox of Choice: Why
118. “In summary both absolute and relative utili- More Is Less (New York: HarperCollins, 2004).
ty effects are active as national happiness varies
with national income. Contrary to strong models 130. Robert E. Lane, The Loss of Happiness in Market

40
Democracies (New Haven: Yale University Press, 131. J. M. Keynes, “Economic Possibilities for our
2000), p. 165. Schwartz quotes a smaller bit of Grandchildren,” in Essays in Persuasion (New York:
this passage in The Paradox of Choice, p. 109. Norton, 1991), p. 367.

41
OTHER STUDIES IN THE POLICY ANALYSIS SERIES

589. Energy Alarmism: The Myths That Make Americans Worry about Oil by
Eugene Gholz and Daryl G. Press (April 5, 2007)

588. Escaping the Trap: Why the United States Must Leave Iraq by Ted Galen
Carpenter (February 14, 2007)

587. Why We Fight: How Public Schools Cause Social Conflict by Neal
McCluskey (January 23, 2007)

586. Has U.S. Income Inequality Really Increased? by Alan Reynolds (January 8, 2007)

585. The Cato Education Market Index by Andrew J. Coulson with advisers
James Gwartney, Neal McCluskey, John Merrifield, David Salisbury, and
Richard Vedder (December 14, 2006)

584. Effective Counterterrorism and the Limited Role of Predictive Data


Mining by Jeff Jonas and Jim Harper (December 11, 2006)

583. The Bottom Line on Iran: The Costs and Benefits of Preventive War
versus Deterrence by Justin Logan (December 4, 2006)

582. Suicide Terrorism and Democracy: What We’ve Learned Since 9/11 by
Robert A. Pape (November 1, 2006)

581. Fiscal Policy Report Card on America’s Governors: 2006 by Stephen


Slivinski (October 24, 2006)

580. The Libertarian Vote by David Boaz and David Kirby (October 18, 2006)

579. Giving Kids the Chaff: How to Find and Keep the Teachers We Need
by Marie Gryphon (September 25, 2006)

578. Iran’s Nuclear Program: America’s Policy Options by Ted Galen Carpenter
(September 20, 2006)

577. The American Way of War: Cultural Barriers to Successful


Counterinsurgency by Jeffrey Record (September 1, 2006)

576. Is the Sky Really Falling? A Review of Recent Global Warming Scare
Stories by Patrick J. Michaels (August 23, 2006)

575. Toward Property Rights in Spectrum: The Difficult Policy Choices Ahead
by Dale Hatfield and Phil Weiser (August 17, 2006)

574. Budgeting in Neverland: Irrational Policymaking in the U.S. Congress


and What Can Be Done about It by James L. Payne (July 26, 2006)
573. Flirting with Disaster: The Inherent Problems with FEMA by Russell S.
Sobel and Peter T. Leeson (July 19, 2006)

572. Vertical Integration and the Restructuring of the U.S. Electricity Industry
by Robert J. Michaels (July 13, 2006)

571. Reappraising Nuclear Security Strategy by Rensselaer Lee (June 14, 2006)

570. The Federal Marriage Amendment: Unnecessary, Anti-Federalist, and


Anti-Democratic by Dale Carpenter (June 1, 2006)

569. Health Savings Accounts: Do the Critics Have a Point? by Michael F.


Cannon (May 30, 2006)

568. A Seismic Shift: How Canada’s Supreme Court Sparked a Patients’


Rights Revolution by Jacques Chaoulli (May 8, 2006)

567. Amateur-to-Amateur: The Rise of a New Creative Culture by F. Gregory


Lastowka and Dan Hunter (April 26, 2006)

566. Two Normal Countries: Rethinking the U.S.-Japan Strategic


Relationship by Christopher Preble (April 18, 2006)

565. Individual Mandates for Health Insurance: Slippery Slope to National


Health Care by Michael Tanner (April 5, 2006)

564. Circumventing Competition: The Perverse Consequences of the Digital


Millennium Copyright Act by Timothy B. Lee (March 21, 2006)

563. Against the New Paternalism: Internalities and the Economics of Self-
Control by Glen Whitman (February 22, 2006)

562. KidSave: Real Problem, Wrong Solution by Jagadeesh Gokhale and Michael
Tanner (January 24, 2006)

561. Economic Amnesia: The Case against Oil Price Controls and Windfall
Profit Taxes by Jerry Taylor and Peter Van Doren (January 12, 2006)

560. Failed States and Flawed Logic: The Case against a Standing Nation-
Building Office by Justin Logan and Christopher Preble (January 11, 2006)

559. A Desire Named Streetcar: How Federal Subsidies Encourage Wasteful


Local Transit Systems by Randal O’Toole (January 5, 2006)

558. The Birth of the Property Rights Movement by Steven J. Eagle (December 15, 2005)

557. Trade Liberalization and Poverty Reduction in Sub-Saharan Africa by


Marian L. Tupy (December 6, 2005)

556. Avoiding Medicare’s Pharmaceutical Trap by Doug Bandow (November 30,


2005)
555. The Case against the Strategic Petroleum Reserve by Jerry Taylor and
Peter Van Doren (November 21, 2005)

554. The Triumph of India’s Market Reforms: The Record of the 1980s and
1990s by Arvind Panagariya (November 7, 2005)

553. U.S.-China Relations in the Wake of CNOOC by James A. Dorn


(November 2, 2005)

552. Don’t Resurrect the Law of the Sea Treaty by Doug Bandow (October 13, 2005)

551. Saving Money and Improving Education: How School Choice Can Help
States Reduce Education Costs by David Salisbury (October 4, 2005)

550. The Personal Lockbox: A First Step on the Road to Social Security
Reform by Michael Tanner (September 13, 2005)

549. Aging America’s Achilles’ Heel: Medicaid Long-Term Care by Stephen A.


Moses (September 1, 2005)

548. Medicaid’s Unseen Costs by Michael F. Cannon (August 18, 2005)

547. Uncompetitive Elections and the American Political System by Patrick


Basham and Dennis Polhill (June 30, 2005)

546. Controlling Unconstitutional Class Actions: A Blueprint for Future


Lawsuit Reform by Mark Moller (June 30, 2005)

545. Treating Doctors as Drug Dealers: The DEA’s War on Prescription


Painkillers by Ronald T. Libby (June 6, 2005)

544. No Child Left Behind: The Dangers of Centralized Education Policy by


Lawrence A. Uzzell (May 31, 2005)

543. The Grand Old Spending Party: How Republicans Became Big Spenders
by Stephen Slivinski (May 3, 2005)

542. Corruption in the Public Schools: The Market Is the Answer by Neal
McCluskey (April 14, 2005)

541. Flying the Unfriendly Skies: Defending against the Threat of Shoulder-
Fired Missiles by Chalres V. Peña (April 19, 2005)

540. The Affirmative Action Myth by Marie Gryphon (April 6, 2005)

539. $400 Billion Defense Budget Unnecessary to Fight War on Terrorism by


Charles V. Peña (March 28, 2005)

You might also like