You are on page 1of 3

Applied Animal Behaviour Science 118 (2009) 105–107

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Applied Animal Behaviour Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/applanim

Editorial

The state of ethological approaches to the assessment of animal suffering


and welfare§

Advances in the neurosciences, in ethology and animal biology (Koch, 2004). Feelings of suffering and well-being
cognition have told us to expect at least some of our fellow are subjective experiences that cannot be assessed directly
creatures to be capable of experiencing affective states by scientific methods, since the natural sciences strictly
such as pain, fear, anxiety, or pleasure. Although covering a adhere to a third person perspective. Therefore, biology has
wide range of discrete emotional experiences, affective long dismissed subjective experiences as a target worthy of
states may all be categorized into states of suffering and scientific investigation, which probably explains why we
well-being. From an ethological perspective what seems to still know rather little about them. In addition, based on an
be important in terms of animal welfare is whether or not epistemological fallacy – what cannot be investigated
an affective state is unpleasant enough for an animal to cannot exist – animals were simply denied the capacity for
want to get out of it (Dawkins, 2008). If it is, it is considered subjective experiences by many scientists.
to reflect suffering, if not, it is considered to reflect well- This is actually surprising, given that pain and suffering
being. This conception provides us with a behavioural way have long been assessed and successfully treated not only
of recognising animal suffering, and has put ethology at the in humans but also in veterinary medical practice. More-
front of animal welfare sciences. over, not even in humans is there a direct way of assessing
However, the assessment of animal welfare is not a subjective experiences. There is no fundamental difference
matter of the natural sciences only. Thus, whether or not a between animals and humans with respect to the scientific
particular behavioural measure is relevant to the assess- assessment of suffering and well-being. Not even language
ment of animal welfare critically depends on the ethical makes a fundamental difference. Although verbal com-
criteria according to which animals are to be protected. munication is a useful tool for medical doctors in the
These ethical criteria are developed by philosophers and diagnosis of human pain or suffering, it is neither
agreed on by society as a whole. They determine the legal unambiguous, nor applicable to all patients.
means by which animal protection is implemented, but also In September 2007, in an attempt to leave this arbitrary
the kind of scientific evidence that counts in the assessment distinction between humans and other animals in the
of animal welfare. Animal ethics is hotly debated, for attribution of affective states behind, the International
example between utilitarian animal welfarists and deonto- Society of Livestock Husbandry (Internationale
logical animal rights advocates (Singer, 1975; Regan, 1983). Gesellschaft für Nutztierhaltung, IGN) together with the
This debate is, however, not the focus of this special issue. Chair of Animal Welfare and Ethology of the Justus-Liebig-
Instead, this special issue is aimed to provide an overview of University of Giessen (Germany) held a scientific sympo-
the state of ethological approaches to the assessment of sium entitled ‘Animal Suffering and Well-Being—Interna-
animal suffering and welfare, based on the ethical principles tional Symposium on the State of Science’. The aim of this
underlying current animal welfare legislation. The focus is symposium was to present and discuss recent advances in
placed on concepts and methods that allow us to assess the study of animal suffering and well-being. The present
animals’ affective states in view of reducing animal suffering special issue is based on contributions to this symposium.
and improving animal well-being. For one thing: what The issue starts with a review by David Fraser on the
animals need for their welfare needs to be justified history of the study of affective states of animals, showing
biologically by the animals’ own values. how this concept varied throughout human history, but
Whether animals do indeed have the capacity to also between ethnic groups and – not least – between
experience feelings of suffering and well-being, still ranks different schools of thought within the natural sciences.
among the hardest and most controversial questions in Based on pioneers such as Jane Goodall, Barbara Smuts and
others, his paper concludes with a plea for the collection of
qualitative, narrative data in addition to quantitative data
§
This paper is part of a special issue entitled ‘‘Animal Suffering and in view of understanding the unique features of individual
Welfare’’, Guest Edited by Hanno Würbel animals. He argues that such data almost require scientists

0168-1591/$ – see front matter ß 2009 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.applanim.2009.02.021
106 Editorial / Applied Animal Behaviour Science 118 (2009) 105–107

to involve affect in order to achieve plausible explanations demand are undoubtedly measures of cognitive or judge-
of behaviour. ment bias. These measures are known from human
Not only how animals ought to be protected, but also cognitive psychology to reflect affective states, especially
why we want to do this, may be an ethological question. emotional valence. Together with colleagues, Mike Mendl
After all, animal protection is human behaviour. In the first and Liz Paul present a comprehensive review of studies on
part of his paper, Hanno Würbel thus takes an ethological rats, dogs, rhesus monkeys, starlings and humans that have
perspective on animal protection with a view to better since been conducted, and discuss the strengths and
understanding how our own behavioural biology shapes weaknesses of different affect manipulation treatments,
our attitude towards animals. This may be crucial in view and other aspects that may affect the observed effects and
of avoiding unjustified anthropocentrism and uncritical their interpretation in terms of affective states. One problem
anthropomorphism. In the second part of the paper, he with current cognitive bias studies is that they require
then reviews concepts and methods used to assess animal extensive training to establish the necessary positive and
welfare in terms of their significance for ethical decision- negative associations. Brilot and colleagues present an
taking, and proposes ethologically meaningful measures of experiment using European starlings’ (Sturnus vulgaris)
‘behavioural integrity’ as potentially powerful indicators of responses to eyespot stimuli that are naturally aversive to
animal welfare. many bird species, and require no explicit associative
Due to the sentientist conception of current animal training. Although their present approach was unsuccessful
welfare legislation, one of the main targets of animal welfare in determining cognitive bias, it may provide important
science is to determine the boundary between sentient and guidance for the future search of measures of cognitive bias
non-sentient animals. Most welfare regulations are that do not depend on extensive associative training.
restricted to vertebrates, and even among vertebrate The past years of animal welfare research have also
scientists, there is debate as to where to draw that boundary. witnessed an extension of focus in the assessment of
Bob Elwood and colleagues review evidence that crusta- animal welfare from using measures of negative affect (i.e.
ceans might experience pain and stress in ways that are suffering) to using measures of both negative and positive
analogous to those of sentient vertebrates. They conclude affect. Manteuffel and colleagues present a review of their
that there is considerable similarity of function, although development and applications of rewarded instrumental
different systems are used, and thus there might be a similar learning as a form of cognitive enrichment, which enables
experience in terms of suffering. In light of their findings, the farm animals to acquire instrumental behaviour that may
treatment of crustaceans – and possibly other invertebrates improve their well-being. They conclude that this
– may need to be reconsidered. Based on a similar case made approach may have the potential to enhance not only
for fish in the recent past, Nicola Brydges and Victoria animal welfare but also product quality in animal farming.
Braithwaite examined whether environmental enrichment This is followed by a paper by Reefmann and colleagues
of housing conditions for fish can have similar effects on who studied whether ear and tail postures in sheep can be
learning, memory and temperament behaviours as found in used as measures of emotional valence from negative to
rodents and many other captive mammals. positive states. They found that frequent ear-posture
In contrast to invertebrates and fish, the assumption changes were most clearly associated with situations
that pigs can experience pain has been unchallenged for a inducing negative states, while a high proportion of
long time. Nevertheless, we still know very little about passive ear postures was associated with situations
nociceptive processes in pigs. Therefore, Mette Herskin inducing positive states. Thus, ear-posture changes repre-
and colleagues set out to validate a laser-based method to sent a promising indicator of emotional valence in sheep.
measure thermal nociception in pigs. Their findings To conclude this section on positive affective states,
suggest that behavioural responses to nociceptive cuta- Jonathan Balcombe reviews the evidence in the literature
neous laser stimulation provide valid measures of noci- for animal pleasure and discusses its moral significance
ception that can be applied in group-housed gilts, with with respect to animal welfare legislation.
minimal disturbance of the daily routines. The final section of this special issue deals with an
One of the most influential concepts in applied ethology important new development in farm animal production,
is the concept of motivational strength based on measures of breeding for disease resistance. Even under the most
demand. The interpretation of measures of demand in the favourable housing and management conditions, infectious
assessment of animal welfare is based on several underlying diseases remain a constant threat to farm animals, and a
assumptions. Lucy Asher and colleagues have tested two serious one as infectious diseases are ranked among the
critical assumptions underlying most studies using mea- major sources of suffering in animal production. In the first
sures of demand to assess animals’ preferences for different paper, Gerald Reiner introduces the approaches taken to
resources. Using European starlings, they demonstrate that genetic disease resistance in pigs. Using Sarcocystis
presenting costs on an ascending order may yield valid miescheriana resistance in pigs as a parasitic disease model,
measures of demand, but that random order presentations he highlights the difficulties in identifying carriers of
should be used to check for order effects. In contrast, they favourable gene variants, and novel tools and technologies
found that the concept of a finite energy budget may not be emerging from recent advances in genomics to tackle these.
useful in the measurement of captive animal’s preferences, In the final paper, Reiner and colleagues then present a
and that a different approach might therefore be needed. detailed behavioural analysis of the course of this parasitic
The most exciting additions to the toolbox of animal model disease. By relating the behavioural changes to
welfare scientists since the introduction of measures of various clinical and clinical–chemical measures, they were
Editorial / Applied Animal Behaviour Science 118 (2009) 105–107 107

able to identify behavioural indicators of disease even at References


sub-clinical stages, suggesting that even sub-clinical con-
Dawkins, M.S., 2008. The science of animal suffering. Ethology 114, 937–
ditions may compromise the pigs’ welfare. 945.
Taken together, the papers compiled in this special Koch, C., 2004. The Quest for Consciousness: A Neuroscientific Approach.
issue reveal the high degree of sophistication by which Roberts & Company Publishers, Englewood.
Regan, T., 1983. The Case for Animal Rights. University of California Press,
ethologists are now able to infer affective states and make Berkeley.
convincing scientific cases for feelings of suffering and Singer, P., 1975. Animal Liberation. Harper Collins Publishers, New York.
well-being in animals. The ethological study of animal
suffering and welfare has thus great potential to add Hanno Würbel*
objectivity to animal welfare debates, and may be crucial Division of Animal Welfare and Ethology,
in facilitating the implementation of the ethical goals Justus-Liebig-University of Giessen,
as stated in animal welfare legislation. However, the 35392 Giessen, Germany
papers compiled in this special issue should also reveal
existing gaps in our knowledge and research, thereby *Tel.: +49 641 99 38750; fax: +49 641 99 38759
contributing to the future advancement of ethology E-mail address: hanno.wuerbel@vetmed.uni-giessen.de
applied to animal ethics and to the improvement of
animal welfare. Available online 17 March 2009

You might also like