You are on page 1of 18

This article was downloaded by: [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] On: 01 October 2013, At: 19:10 Publisher:

Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

Australasian Journal of Philosophy


Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rajp20

The teleological theory of content


David Braddon-Mitchell
a b a b

& Frank Jackson

a b

University of Auckland

Australian National University Published online: 02 Jun 2006.

To cite this article: David Braddon-Mitchell & Frank Jackson (1997) The teleological theory of content, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75:4, 474-489, DOI: 10.1080/00048409712348051 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00048409712348051

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the Content) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013 and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-andconditions

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 75, No. 4; December 1997

THE TELEOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONTENT David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson The teleological theory of content is an attractive package. The first part is the plausible contention that we are a biological part of nature - biology is the science that studies us qua human beings. The second part is a plausible analysis: the aetiological cure evolutionary analysis of function in biology - roughly, a biological state's function is what it was selected for; or, in Ruth Millikan's terminology, function in biology is proper function.~ These parts get combined with a thesis about intentional states, namely, that the right approach to their content is via the recognition that they have a function in the sense of a telos: if you want to find the content of an intentional state, look to what it is for. But intentional states are biological states, so, from the thesis that function in biology is proper function, we end up with the teleological theory of content (or teleonomy, as we will sometimes say for short), the thesis that an intentional state's content is given by its proper function. Here is how the story often runs in the case of belief. Belief is a state whose function is to represent how things are. This means that the content of a belief is the particular way things are which the belief has the function of co-varying with. But, then, by the aetiological analysis of function in biology, it follows that the content of a belief is the way things are or the state of affairs with which the belief was selected to co-vary. For example, belief that there is water nearby is, roughly, the state whose presence in us is explained by the way its induction by nearby water was selectionally advantageous, and it gets to have the content that there is water nearby because of this. In similar fashion, starting this time from the premise that the function of desires is to represent how things should be, we reach the conclusion that the content of a desire is the state of affairs it was selected to make obtain. Thus, roughly, desire to be near water is the state whose presence in us is explained by the way its tendency to make us be near water was selectionally advantageous, and this is how it comes to have the content it does have. Which aspect of selectional history determines content varies from one version of teleonomy to another. Famously, certain frogs respond equally to flies and to any small, dark, moving things. This is because, although it was important to the frogs' survival that they detected flies, the vast majority of small, dark moving things that they came across were in fact flies, and so it did not matter that their fly detectors could not tell the difference. On some teleological theories, this means that their fly detectors, strictly speaking, only represent that there is a small, dark, moving thing within tongue range. 2 On most teleological theories, though, their fly detectors really do represent that there is a fly t Ruth Millikan, Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984). See, e.g., Karen Neander, 'Misrepresenting and Malfunctioning', Philosophical Studies 79 (1995) pp.109-141.

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

474

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

475

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

within tongue range, because it mattered for survival that what got ingested were flies. Again, teleological theories differ over whether it is evolutionary history alone, or whether (as in 'neural Darwinism') quite recent selectional history also matters for content, and hence over what to say about beliefs and desires concerning kinds of things that were not around when we were shaped by evolution. Again, some teleological theories focus on the relational proper function of the mechanism that gives rise to a state rather than on the state's own proper function: a state is about such and such if it is produced by a mechanism whose proper function is to produce that state when such and such. We will abstract from these important details. Our initial concern is with the status of the view that understands content in terms of selectional history. Are teleonomists offering us a conceptual analysis, or are they making a claim about essential properties, or are they putting forward a scientific identification or theoretical reduction of intentional content? In the first half of this paper, we argue that they must be doing the third. In the second half, we argue, on the basis of this understanding of their view, that it faces two serious objections. Our arguments in both parts are independent of the details about which aspects of selectional history have the claimed special relationship to content; our focus will be on various views about what that special relationship might be and the problems attendant on these views. (Also, we will frame matters in terms of teleonomies that focus on the selectional histories of the contentful states, but the same points apply mutatis mutandis to versions that focus on the relational proper functions of the mechanisms that produce the states.) Further, we will collapse the distinction between selectional views and teleological views. Strictly, it is biological function that teleonomy holds to be crucial for the determination of content, and selectional history enters the picture only inasmuch as a selectional-cum-aetiological account of biological function is correct; but the most interesting and discussed versions of the teleological account of content assume, or argue for in an earlier chapter or paper or book, a selectional-cum-aetiological account of function in biology - the function as proper function account - and we will be concerned only with this style of teleonomy.

It is not in dispute that there is a close, non-accidental connection between content and selectional history. The belief that there is water nearby is important for survival in part because of its connection with their being water nearby. This means that, in light of the overwhelming evidence in favour of the theory of evolution, we can be confident that this fact played a major role in our tending to have the belief that there is water nearby when appropriate. Likewise, the desire for food is important for survival because of its connection with the consumption of food; so we can be confident, on evolutionary grounds, that this connection played a major role in our sometimes having the desire for food. In short, it is very plausible that, in very many cases, the states of affairs that beliefs and desires are about, their contents, played an important role in our having the beliefs and desires in the first place. David Papineau expresses his version of teleonomy by saying that, roughly, the belief that p is the state selected to co-vary with p, and the desire that p is the state selected to

476

The Teleological Theory of Content

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

bring about p ? This is not merely the claim that we can, on evolutionary grounds, be confident that, by and large, there is a non-accidental connection between the obtaining of p and having the belief that p, and there is a non-accidental connection between the bringing about o f p and having the desire that p : Teleonomy only becomes an interesting theory when it goes beyond this common ground observation. But how might it do so? One answer is to treat it as a matter of conceptual analysis that the content of beliefs and desires is determined by selectional history (whether in the way Papineau favours or notS). Now, most teleonomists insist that they are not advancing a conceptual analysis. Some, Millikan notably, do this as part of a general scepticism about the project of offering c o n c e p t u a l a n a l y s e s - ' " c o n c e p t u a l a n a l y s i s " . . . is a c o n f u s e d p r o g r a m , a philosophical chimera, a squaring of the c i r c l e . . . ,.6 Others, Karen Neander, for example, grant the propriety of conceptual analysis - indeed see it as having an important place in the overall case for teleonomy - while insisting that the claim that content is given by selectional history is not itself a piece of conceptual analysis. 7 We think conceptual analysis is essential to much work in philosophy, but agree that teleonomists had better not be offering their selectional account of content as pure conceptual analysis. Despite the agreement, we need to argue the matter, as the points that come up will be important later. To offer a conceptual analysis of K-hood is, as we understand it, to offer an illuminating account of what, implicitly or explicitly, guides those who understand the term 'K' in classifying something as a K. The role of the reflections on possible cases associated with conceptual analysis is to help articulate what is guiding us in our classificatory practice. The famous illustration of this role is the debate over the analysis of knowledge. It is tempting to think that the term 'knowledge' is a short expression covering cases of true justified belief; however, by describing possible cases of true justified belief which are true by accideilt but justified all the same, Edmund Gettier convinced us that classifying by knowledge is not classifying by true justified belief? This account of conceptual analysis may make it sound a purely descriptive exercise - it is simply a matter of finding the best description o f what in fact guides our classifications - but there is a normative dimension to conceptual analysis. The terms and concepts whose conceptual analysis is worth taking time over - like the concepts of free action, content, and knowl: 3 David Papineau, Philosophical Naturalism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), p.94. 4 We talk here of 'by and large, non-accidental connections' rather than typical ones in order to side-step the important, but here irrelevant, debates over whether and to what extent evolutionary considerations support our beliefs being typically true and our desires being typically satisfied. 5 Some supporters of teleonomy favour a more complex account that sees the contents of parts of intentional states - the words of mentalese - as determined by selectional history, and then accounts for the contents of the intentional-states themselves compositionally. As far as we can see, the added complexity of the LOT approach does not buy a reply to the objections we raise in the second half of this paper. 6 Ruth Millikan, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambridge, /vIA: MIT Press, 1993), p.15. 7 According to Neander, the place of conceptual analysis in the overall story is much as we sketched at the beginning. Puzzlingly, Millikan, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays, p. 15, fn. 1, remarks that Neander offers 'a brilliant defence of the "etiological" account of function while remaining within the tradition of conceptual analysis'. We are not sure how one pursues 'a confused program, a philosophical chimera, a squaring of the circle' brilliantly. 8 Edmund L. Gettier, 'Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?', Analysis 23 (1963) pp.121-123.

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

477

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

edge, and unlike the concept of a bicycle (who cares much if we decide to count a tricycle as a special sort of bicycle?) - play important roles in our theories. In consequence, we need to ask of any proffered analysis whether it is fit to play the needed theoretical role: an analysis of free action should make sense of the connection between acting freely and being liable for punishment, an analysis of content should make sense of its role in our theories of mind and language, and so on. This gives us a 'one sentence' answer to critics of conceptual analysis. How can it be wrong (or confused, or chimerical, or a squaring of the circle) to seek to make explicit what guides us in the intentional and considered activity of classifying things as falling under one or another interesting term or concept, especially when it is informed by the desideratum of making good sense of the term or concept's theoretical role? It will now be clear why teleonomy cannot be a conceptual claim. Creationists understand content clauses perfectly well. So did people before the theory of evolution was put forward and the notion of a selectional history became common currency in biology. It is absurd to suppose that these people could come up with the theory of evolution simply by careful enough reflection on when they counted someone as believing that snow is white or desiring coffee, and, more generally, on what underlies their classifying someone as having one or another belief or desire. Their classifying Jones as believing that snow is white - as one of the things that believe that snow is white, as opposed to one of the things that do not - has nothing to do with their holding, implicitly or explicitly, that Jones' belief state is in some way selected for by the whiteness of snow, and yet that is what would have to be the case if the selectional account were a conceptual truth. II. The second suggestion is that we should read teleonomy's distinctive claim as that selectional history is an essential property of contentful states - much as being H 2 0 is an essential property of water, and having atomic number 79 is an essential property of gold. According to this reading, it is an a posteriori scientific discovery about the nature of contentful intentional states that selectional histories of a certain kind are essential properties of them. Now, we can think of essential properties in the transworld identity way principally associated with Saul Kripke, or in the counterpart way principally associated with David Lewis .9 On the transworld identity way of thinking about essential properties, an essential property of something is simply a property which that very thing has in every world where it occurs. Construing essential properties in this way makes life difficult for the teleonomist. What has the right kind of selectional history are certain physical states in our brains. ' They are those particular states and structures that evolution has bequeathed 9 See, e.g., Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1980), and David Lewis, 'Counterparts of Persons and Their Bodies', The Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971) pp.203-211. ,0 We talk of physical states rather than neurological or brain states because teleonomists often insist that for a state to be properly described using the terms 'neurological' or "brain" it must have a suitable selectional history, and it makes it easier to grasp the point that follows to use a term we can all agree lacks any implications about any particular selectional history. We take 'physical' to be such a term, but anyone who disagrees can of course plug in their own candidate to be the needed neutral term.

478

The Teleological Theory of Content

to us in order to help us find our way around and get what we need to survive. And it is not an essential property of any physical state, S, that it has a certain selectional history: S might have had a different selectional history from the one it actually has. This is true even if S's causal origin is one of its essential properties. In this case the different selectional history must start at the same place, but this is consistent with the selectional history itseff being different. Different selectional histories set in different environments can take one from a given starting point to the very same S. This point stands independently of a claim about biological kinds often made by teleonomists. They argue that in biology we type by proper function: a kidney is that which has a certain proper function, not that which meets a certain anatomical specification (or, for that matter, performs a certain current function)." Nevertheless, each and every (natural) kidney is a certain anatomical structure, namely, the anatomical structure with the right proper function, and it is not an essential property of that anatomical structure that it has the selectional history it in fact has. Of course, on the view about biological kinds in question, if that structure lacked the right selectional history, it would not count as a kidney - in which case being a kidney would not be an essential property of kidneys, just as being Prime Minister is not an essential property of Prime Ministers. In the same way, what has the selectional histories that are, according to teleonomy, distinctive of intentional content are certain physical structures, but it is not an essential property of these structures that they have this history; and this is true consistently with their having these histories being what matters in biological theory and what makes it right to describe them as content-bearing states. So, on the Kripkean way of thinking about essential properties, it is false that any particular selectional history is an essential property of intentional states. However, teleonomists sometimes talk of the very same physical structure having different essences relative to the different 'states' that it can be said to be in: thus, a physical structure qua neurological state is said to have different essential properties from the same physical structure qua contentful state. This suggests that if we want to read teleonomy as a claim about essential properties, we should adopt the alternative, counterpart way of thinking about essential properties; for, on that approach, something's essential properties are not an all or nothing matter, but are relative to one or another counterpart relation. The counterpart approach is set against a background that denies transworld identity. According to it (albeit roughly, since the details of various versions of counterpart theory are irrelevant here), an essential property of x is a property of x that every counterpart of x has in every world in which it exists, where a counterpart of x in a world is something very similar to x, not x itself. But what counts as very similar depends on which respects of similarity are salient; in consequence~ a thing's counterparts can vary depending on which similarity is salient, or, as it is put, a thing can have different counterparts under different counterpart relations. This is why, according to counterpart theory, a thing's essential properties are not an all or nothing matter. For example, the counterparts of some physical structure, S, which is simultaneously a certain neurological state, a certain contentful state, and a certain physical configuration, will vary depending on whether we ~t See, e.g., Karen Neander, 'Swampman meets Swampcow', Mind and Language 11 (1996) pp.118-129, for a recent defence of this view.

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

479

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

look to what, in other worlds, counts as very similar going by neurological nature, by content, or by physical structure; in consequence, what counts as S's essential properties depends on the counterpart relation in play. This complicates the discussion of the reading of teleonomy as the view that selectional history is an essential property of contentful states. For when teleonomists say that a certain selectional history is an essential property of a contentful state, they say, according to the counterpart way of understanding essential properties, that every counterpart of it shares the certain selectional history. But which counterpart relation or relations should they be taken as working with? It would obviously be a mistake to be too liberal and say that any reasonable answer as to a contentful state C's counterparts in other possible worlds will do. C will, for example, be a particular physical structure, and so, under the physical-structure counterpart relation, anything physically exactly like C will be a counterpart of C, but physical duplicates in other worlds can, and do, have different selectional histories. The right counterpart relation for teleonomists is, we suggest, the same-content relation; that is, the best way to read teleonomy as a claim about essential properties is as the claim that a certain selectional history is an essential property of contentful states under the same-content counterpart relation. But, to see why this is so, we need to have before us the scientific reduction reading of teleonomy. 1II. The final reading of teleonomy is as a scientific reduction or identification of content the identification of content with selectional history is of a piece with the identifications of lightning with an electrical discharge, of water with H 2 0 , and of heat in ideal gases with molecular kinetic energy. This is the suggestion most often found in the writings of teleonomists and will be the one discussed critically in the second half of this paper. 12 (Indeed, except when explicit note to the contrary is made, from now on we mean by 'teleonomy' teleonomy so understood.) But first we need to detail briefly this way of understanding teleonomy. Although the identification of lightning with an electrical discharge is not a piece of conceptual analysis, the identification did not, of course, come from nowhere. There was a case to be made for it that involved observations about what we use the word 'lightning' for. (What follows abbreviates a much told story, so we say it quickly.) Roughly, the case starts from the point that 'lightning' is a word for a phenomenon that plays a certain role - not in the sense that the word means that which plays the role, but in the sense that the role does the reference-fixing - and concludes with the point that, as a matter of fact, what plays the role is an electrical discharge. ~3 This is how the sentence 'Lightning is an electrical discharge' gets its famous necessary a posteriori status. It is a posteriori because it is a posteriori that it is an electrical discharge that plays the role. It David Papineau is especially explicit that he is offering a reduction, see Philosophical Naturalism, p.93. To put the matter in terms of Kdpke's distinction between giving the meaning and fixing the reference in Naming and Necessity. You might well regard an account of what reference-fixes as part of an account of meaning in a wide sense, but what matters here is that there is an important distinction, not the words used to mark it. We will follow Kripke's usage because of its familiarity.

480

The Teleological Theory of Content

is necessary because playing the role reference-fixes on an electrical discharge, and this means that 'lightning' refers to an electrical discharge in all worlds (in which it exists, but we will suppress complications arising from the possibility of non-existence in a world), regardless of whether or not electrical discharge plays the role in those wodds. The result is that 'Lightning is an electrical discharge' is true in all worlds. In the same way, a scientific identification of content with selectional history has, or should have, two parts. The first says something about what we folk use words like

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

'believes that snow is white' and 'desires a cup of coffee' for, in the sense of the usages we need to master to understand these phrases. This is given by what are sometimes called the folk markers for the phrases; TM or we can talk in terms of reference-fixing, as we just have in the case of lightning. The second part says that what we reference-fix on, what the folk markers pick out, are, as it happens, states-with-a-certain-selectional-history. This means that what counts as a state with a certain content in some possible world is the state with right selectional history in that world, regardless of whether or not it satisfies the folk markers in that world. This then delivers an interesting, necessary a posteriori identification of content states with states with the right selectional history, which goes well beyond the common ground observation that there is a non-accidental association between content and selectional history. How should the folk markers or reference-fixers be characterised? In the cases of temperature, water, and lightning, there are reasonably non-controversial answers. The situation is, as so often, more controversial in the case of words for intentional states. We will offer what seems to us the most promising approach to the characterisation of the folk markers or reference-fixers for intentional content. As far as we can see, it does not beg any important questions to come; the points we make later could be made against the background of any reasonable account of the folk markers. Language is primarily a convention-generated system of communication. We use it to tell one another how things are, by means of implicit agreements concerning when to use various words and sentences. Coming to understand a language is coming to understand when to use the various terms - 'rouge' is the word to use in French when confronted with something you take to be red, and so on. Now what did we learn when we came to understand phrases like 'believes that snow is white' and 'desires a cup of coffee'? As we observed when rejecting the reading of teleonomy as a piece of conceptual analysis, we did not learn to use these words for creatures with states having a certain selectional history. For we learnt something that could be accepted by creationists and those who have never heard of the theory of evolution. W e learnt, rather, to use these terms for organisms having states that lead to the display of certain complex interaction patterns with their environment. For it is the observation of the complex interaction patterns which prompts in speakers (and writers) claims about what people believe and desire. It is after learning what people do (and say in the case of creatures with a language) that the folk come to opinions about what subjects think and want. W e can sum this up by saying that teleonomists do best to hold that the folk markers or reference-fixers for intentional states are folk functional roles. ~5 t4 See, e.g., Michael Devitt, Coming to Our Senses: a naturalistic program for semantic localism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996). ,5 And Papineau does exactly this; see his response to Andrew Woodfield on pp.93-94 of Philosophical Naturalism.

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

481

We can now set out their argument for the a posteriori identification or reduction of intentional content to proper function, as follows. P1 Belief that p is the theoretically interesting state that actually plays the folk functional roles distinctive of belief that p (from reflection on what we master when we master intentional vocabulary). The theoretically interesting state that actually plays the folk functional roles distinctive of belief that p is the state selected to do what belief that p is for qua state so selected (from the fact that biology is the relevant theory for intentional creatures like us, combined with the etiological account of function in biology). Con. Belief that p is the state selected to do what belief that p is for. The conclusion will have the status typical of interesting scientific identifications; it will be necessary a posteriori. A view of this general kind seems to us to be the most interesting and plausible style of teleonomy, and to be closest to what teleonomists say about how their view should be understood. It entails a claim about essential properties under a suitable counterpart relation. If it is necessary a posteriori that belief that p, in particular, and contentful states, in general, have certain selectional histories, then everything that has the same content as some contentful state has the same selectional history in the relevant respect; that is to say, this selectional history is an essential property of it under the same-content counterpart relation. This is why we said, at the end of the previous section, that this is the right version of the essential properties reading of teleonomy. Teleonomy read as a scientific identification or reduction seems to us to face two serious objections, and, as heralded early on, the second half of this paper is concerned with these objections. IV. The first turns on the claim that teleonomy cannot be offered as the theory of content. At best, it is a theory of one kind of content. In the previous section, we outlined the Lockean conception of language as a system of communication, as something in the same general family as morse code and semaphore. Accordingly, one good thing to mean by the term of art 'content' in connection with belief is that it is how we take things to be which we often succeed in communicating to one another by using a language we both understand. When Jones says to Smith, 'There is a tiger nearby', the content of what Jones believes is what Jones is typically seeking to convey to Smith by using these words. Likewise, the content of desire is what we often convey to one another about how we would like things to be with sentences we both understand like 'Let's have coffee' and 'Please turn on the air conditioner'. We will call this role of content its informational role. It concerns the information we transfer by means of language about how we take and want things to be - the information about the states of affairs which we take and want to obtain, or the truth conditions which we take

P2

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

482

The Teleological Theory of Content

and want to be satisfied, or the possible combination of objects and properties which we take and want to be the actual combination, or the set of possible worlds which we take or want our world to be a member o f - to mention just some of the options for characterising content. Now it is obvious that informational content is not identified in the sense of being picked out and thereby made known to those seeking to transfer the information, via selectional history. The information we transfer to one another with the kinds of sentences understood equally by believers in evolution, creationists, and those who have never heard of the theory of evolution or of a selectional history, is not identified by selectional history. This is because they do not know or believe the relevant selectional history. When Shakespeare talked to his friends, he was not using a convention-based system that identified certain states of affairs (to settle on that way of characterising-content in order to formulate the point), via the kind of selectional facts that feature in teleonomy, as the ones he took or wanted to obtain, and was anxious to tell his friends about - and the same goes for his friends. He and his friends obviously had some way of making known to each other how they took and wanted things to be, but it was not via their (non-existent) knowledge of selectional histories. Teleonomists are well aware of this point, and often mention it, or something like it, when they explain that they are not offering a conceptual analysis. Although we are contrasting selectional and informational approaches to identifying content, we are not committing ourselves to the view that there are two distinct notions of content in the sense that they concern different states of affairs (sets of worlds, truth conditions, etc.). It may well be that the selectional account often picks out the very same states of affairs as those Shakespeare and his friends picked out, in whatever way they did, when they sought to tell each other how they took and wanted things to be. It is useful to have a name for the way they came to know (when they did) the states of affairs they were telling each other about as ones they took to obtain, or ones they wanted to obtain. We will call it the folk way, to mark the fact that most of us have mastered it, and did so without knowing about the theory of evolution. In these terms, our point is that informational contents are the states of affairs identified in the folk way, and, though the folk way is not that of going by selectional history, the states of affairs identified in the folk way may, nevertheless, overlap with the states of affairs identified selectionally. (The extent to which they do depends on the matters of important detail we set aside at the beginning of the paper.) Moreover, there is an obvious way for teleonomy to incorporate the informational side of content. We argued that teleonomy, in its most plausible version, is in part a view about reference-fixing: we reference-fix by folk functional roles. But folk functional roles are common knowledge. That is what makes them folk. They are, thus, plausible candidates to be what underpins what we have just called the folk way of knowing about content; the way of which we, creationists, and Shakespeare share a mastery. Hence, although people in Shakespeare's time did not have a clue about the selectional histories of their intentional states, and so could not be drawing on this non-existent knowledge when they swapped information about how they took and wanted things to be, they did know about their states' typical causes and effects and, more generally, their folk roles. Hence, teleonomists can explain the informational role of content in terms of the states of affairs on which the folk roles reference-fix. The point here is similar to a point often

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

483

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

made about the information conveyed by using a word like 'water'. What information is conveyed by a sentence like 'There is water nearby' to those who understand it well enough but do not know that water is H 2 0 ? Not that there is H 2 0 nearby. An attractive answer is obtained by drawing on the reference-fixers for 'water'. The information conveyed is that the clear, potable stuff of our acquaintance which falls from the sky, fills the oceans and is known as 'water' in our language community, is nearby. Where is the objection in all this? Why should acknowledging informational content alongside selectional content be a problem for teleonomists? The trouble is that their remarks are evangelical rather than ecumenical. They argue, for example, that only the teleological theory can capture the normative dimension of content. This claim is prominent in Millikan's presentations of teleonomy - famously, her choice of the phrase 'proper function' in describing her view is no accident - but, in the interests of widening the net, we will consider Colin McGinn' s presentation of the claim. We cannot, it seems, recover the content of a representation (conceptual or linguistic) simply from the way it is actually used or is disposed to be used. This is fundamentally because representations can always be used i n c o r r e c t l y . . . The general point here is that we can partition the totality of uses (actual or potential) into two sets, the correct and the incorrect; but this partitioning cannot be effected without employing a notion not definable simply from the notion of bare use, actual or dispositional, viz. the normative notion of using a representation as it ought to be used given its content. It is thus a condition of adequacy upon any account of content that it provide for this distinction among u s e s . . . Here the teleological theory scores valuable points. For it is similarly true that proper function is not definable dispositionaUy: what a trait or organ is supposed to do cannot be deduced from what it is causally disposed to do. You cannot deduce a norm f r o m a fact. 16 This is misleading advertising. The teleological theory does seek to deduce a norm from a fact: something's selectional history is a fact about it. The difference between theories that focus on, for example, actual, current functional roles (which we can think of as the most plausible way to extend the roles McGinn has in mind when he talks of current actual and potential uses) and teleological theories that bring selectional history into the picture, is not that the latter refuse to deduce a norm from a fact; it, rather, concerns the kinds of facts from which the norms are deduced: aetiological facts have a special place in the latter that they do not have in the former. McGinn is fight that there is a problem raised by the normativity of content, but the problem is not especially easy for teleonomists. Moreover, because informational content clearly has a normative dimension there is an important difference between right and wrong ways of conveying information, and right and wrong information, about how things are - and yet informational content is not, as we have seen, delivered by selectional history, there had better be a Colin McGinn, Mental Content (Oxford: Blackwell, 1989), pp.159-160. The final emphasis is ours. McGinn's phrasings here might suggest that he is primarily interested in the content of (public) language, but in fact he takes the point he is making to apply quite generally. We (and most teleonomists) take the content of intentional states to be the primary notion, and hold that language is contentful inasmuch as it is used to tell about the content of various intentional states.

484

The Teleological Theory of Content

non-aetiological way of accounting for its normativity; it had better be the case that selectional history is not the only way to account for the normativity of content. Teleological theorists also argue that only they can handle a well-known 'embarrassment of riches' problem that arises for certain functionalist treatments of content, a problem that derives from the fact that one and the same state has many.different, possible and actual, causes and effects. Here is a typical passage, this time from Papineau's critical discussion of the idea that some version of 'arms length' or commonsense functionalism might explain how our intentional states might be about happenings in the

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

world around us He frames matters in terms of truth conditions of beliefs and satisfaction conditions of desires. why not [in the account of functionalism] simply extend our causal net to allow

more distal causes of perception, on the input side, and more distal effects of behaviour, on the output side? This would allow us to analyse the truth conditions of beliefs as those distal circumstances which cause them, and the satisfaction conditions of desires as those distal states of affairs they give rise t o . . . This move, however, is fatally afflicted by the disease known as 'disjunctivitis'. The belief that there is an ice-cream in front of you can be caused not only by a real icecream, but also by a plastic ice-cream, or a hologram of an ice-cream, or and so on. So, on the current suggestion, the belief in question ought to represent either-a-real-

ice-cream-or-a~plastic-one-or-any-of-the-other-things-that-might-fool-you.

Which of

course it doesn't. Similarly with desires. The results which follow any given desire include not only the real object of the desire, but also various unintended consequences So the current suggestion would imply that the object of any desire is the disjunction of its real object with all those unintended consequences. Which of course it isn't. So even if we widen functionalism's causal roles to include distal causes and effects, we still need somehow to winnow out, from the various causes that give rise to beliefs, and the various results that eventuate from desires, those which the beliefs are about, and which the desires are for. This is where an appeal to teleological considerations seems to yield a natural and satisfying answer. W e can pick out a desire's real satisfaction condition as that effect which it is the desire's biological purpose to produce. And, similarly, we can pick out the real truth conditions of a belief as that which it is the biological purpose of the belief to be co-present with. t7 Papineau is right that there is a major problem here for the simple version of commonsense functionalism that he cites, and it may be that one way of solving it is to appeal to selectional history. But we can be certain that it is not the only way. We do succeed in conveying to one another useful, not hopelessly disjunctive information about how things are. Informational content is no chimera. But, as we have noted, informational David Papineau, PhilosophicalNaturalism, p.58. Kim Sterelny, The Representational Theory of Mind (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990), pp. 124-125, also sees teleological considerations as providing 'more discriminatory machinery', but gives them a much more circumscribed role than does Papineau.

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

485

content is not identified via selectional history. Shakespeare successfully conveyed and received information about how things are. He often knew not hopelessly disjunctive things about what he and his friends thought - he knew the states of affairs (or truth conditions, o r . . . ) that they had in mind - despite not knowing about selectional history, and so not being able to use it to tell him what these states of affairs were. There must, therefore, be some other, folk way of solving the problem Papineau points to (though it would be beyond the remit of this paper to speculate in any detail about what it might be). Further, we know that the winnowing proceeds in a systematic way without reference to

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

selectional history. Suppose that yesterday we thought that there was an ice-cream in a certain shop window, and today we discover that the 'ice-cream' is in fact plastic; we move rationally to the judgement that we were mistaken yesterday. We do it, and things like it, every day of our lives. We grant that it is hard to give a theory of exactly how it is done - to say that we do it by appeal to a folk theory is to say little more than that we folk can do it - but we know that doing it does not depend on using information about selectional history, because very many of those folk who do it lack the relevant information about selectional history. Maxim: if something is done without appeal to such and such, then it can be done without appeal to such and such. There is a general point to b~ made here, not limited to the (important) problems of normativity and winnowing. Once we acknowledge that there is informational content as well as selectional content, and that both are properly to be counted notions of content, it cannot be that there is some problem for content as such that only teleonomy can handle. Teleonomy is not an approach to content that solves certain famous difficulties that defeat all other approaches. Our first objection, then, is that teleonomy cannot be thought of as the one true theory of content, but, at best, as identifying a notion of content that exists alongside informational content (and maybe other kinds as well, but we will not pursue that issue here). It is worth noting that we could have made our key point against Papineau on the winnowing problem without invoking the informational role of content. Although we made the point in terms of it, we did not have to. This means that denying (heroically, as we see things) informational content does not buy a reply to our objection to Papineau. We saw that the best version of teteonomy sees it as a theory reduction that delivers an a posteriori scientific identification of the content of a state with the states of affairs that play some specified role in the state's selectional history. W e also noted that a posteriori scientific identifications rest on views about reference-fixing (or folk markers). The

identification of heat in gases with kinetic energy goes via a view about how we reference-fix on heat - the usual view being that we do so via its filling a certain functional role; and, in the same way, the path to the identification of content with, say, proper function goes via a view about how we reference-fix on content. We suggested, in agreem e n t w i t h P a p i n e a u , t h a t the m o s t p l a u s i b l e v i e w for t e l e o n o m i s t s is t h a t we reference-fix on content via folk functional roles; but, in any case, it is clear that we do not reference-fix via proper function, because we are able to talk about content in ignorance of proper function.~8 'g Moreover, if we did reference-fix by proper function, the identity of content with proper function would be a priori true, contrary to the views of virtually every teleonomist.

486

The Teleological Theory of Content

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

This means that there must be a solution to the winnowing problem that does not appeal to selectional history. Although Papineau is right that a functionalist approach to content needs somehow to winnow out, from the various causes that give rise to beliefs, and the various results that eventuate from desires, those which the beliefs are about, and which the desires are for, and that the simple version of commonsense functionalism he sketches cannot do the job without supplementation, we can be sure that the winnowingout job can be done without appeal to selectional history. For we are able to reference-fix on content - and, on pain of losing the best version of their theory, teleonomists must grant that we are able to reference-fix on content - but we do this, as Papineau himself allows, without appeal to selectional history. If, as we and Papineau agree, the folk roles serve to reference-fix on content, then, somehow or other, we can do the needed.winnowing out without appeal to selectional history. V. Our second and final objection to teleonomy calls for a modicum of stage setting. According to a tradition associated with Descartes, a person's identity over time is not secured by the kinds of physical and psychological continuities much discussed in the recent literature, the kinds that ground our best opinions about personal identity; rather, it is secured by the numerical identity through time of a certain subject of experience, the subject Hume found so elusive. One objection to this view is that we have no good reason to believe in the existence of this mysterious subject of experience, but the most influential objection is the one associated with Locke, the 'who cares' objection. The point behind this objection is that questions of personal identity matter; our personal relations, the institutions of punishment and reward, and our assignments of responsibility are structured around how we individuate persons. If personal identity is, somehow or other, a matter of the much-discussed continuities, we can make good sense of why questions of personal identity matter. We have, for example, at least the beginnings of an idea of why it is typically right to punish the person who did the evil deed rather than someone else altogether. But it is deeply obscure why we should care about the numerical identity over time of the notoriously elusive subject of experience. Similar considerations apply against G. E. M o o r e ' s view that goodness is an unanalysable, non-natural property. ~9 One objection is that we have no good reason to believe that this mysterious property is ever instantiated, but the most influential objection is that it is deeply obscure why we should care whether or not it is instantiated. We would not take seriously someone who said, 'How lucky it is that happiness, honesty and truth are associated with this special, non-natural, unanalysable property goodness, otherwise we could not approve of happiness, honesty and truth'. What we care about is the presence of happiness, honesty, and truth, and the absence of misery, dishonesty, and error; the presence or absence of some further unanalysable, non-natural property is neither here nor there. We think a similar point applies against the selectional account of content. It does not cohere with the way we care about content. Our first objection to teleonomy was that '~ G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1929), 6ff

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

487

reflection on the informational role of content shows that we can and do identify content independently of selectional history, and that this fact undermines the arguments advanced for teleonomy. Our second objection is that we do not value selectional history in the right way for it to determine content in the sense in which we care about the content of what we believe and desire. It at best determines the content we do not care enough about. It has been widely noted that prosthetic surgery for the brain and central nervous system is no more problematic in principle than prosthetic surgery in general. Just as it is sensible to replace a defective heart valve with an artificial one that does the job the original valve did before the deterioration, so it would be sensible to replace defective brain circuits with silicon chips if they did better what was wanted and needed. A common thought experiment is to imagine that, as parts of someone's brain degenerate, they are progressively replaced by silicon implants, and to note that, provided the implants fill the pre-degeneration functional roles of the parts they replace, the surgery counts as successful. The key point for us is that what a patient facing such an operation will care about is essentially that what is about to be inserted in her brain will do the job done by the relevant brain states before things started to go wrong. Our objection is that teleonomists have to deny this, or else embrace the conclusion that content does not matter. According to them, the selectional history of an implant is of vital importance to content. This means that if the patient cares about the content of her beliefs and desires, she should be vitally concerned not merely with whether or not the implant will fill the pre-degeneration input-output function of the brain structure that it replaces, but also with the selectional history of the implant; for that is crucial to the beliefs and desires that it is possible to have as a result of the implant, according to her. But it is very implausible that our patient should regard the selectional history of the implant as an additional thing to worry about over and above what the implant will do, how long it will last, how much the operation will cost, the appearance of the scar, and such like. (We have been asked whether we would extend this objection to the proper function account of function in biology. Would we argue that because we would all choose an artificial heart that did the right things here and now ahead of one with an impeccable pedigree but which had a tendency to malfunction on occasion, there is something wrong with the proper function account of function in biology? We would not, and the reason is that there is a crucial difference between the two cases. The contents of our beliefs and desires are central to our whole conception of what we are like, what is important and worth caring about, and our place in the world - and also to the more mundane business of getting around from day to day - in ways that function in biology does not begin to approach. The idea of becoming like Hitler horrifies us precisely because of what Hitler believed and desired; scientists devote themselves to finding the grand unified theory or a cure for cancer, and that is to devote themselves to acquiring certain kinds of belief; and, on the more mundane level, the passage we carve through the world day by day is shaped by how we take things to be and how we want them to be.) It might be objected that, in the case of silicon implants, we should not focus on the history of the physical structures themselves, but, rather, on the history of the relevant input-output functions. We should be concerned with ensuring that the patient ends up

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

488

The Teleological Theory of Content

with input-output functions that have the right evolutionary history, even if in an indirect way. These indirect ways might include the intentions or history of the makers of the chips (they designed them with the input-output function they have because of the makers' own evolutionary histories), or the intentions or history of the surgeon as they bear on the input-output function. But switching to the selectional history of the input-output function of the implant, rather than that of the implant itself, does not affect our basic point. It is just as implausible that our patient should regard the intentions of, say, the implant's maker concerning the input-output function as a crucial additional thing to worry about, over and above what the implant will do, how long it will last, and the like, as it is to regard the creator's intentions regarding the implant as an additional thing to worry about. And it would be no more sensible for a patient to ask for an implant to be removed and done over again in exactly the same way because of a concern about the intentions of the surgeon with respect to the input-output function, as it would be to ask for the replacement because of a concern about the surgeon's intentions with respect to the implant itself. Teleonomists who insist that we should take a holistic, anti-language of thought, approach to what has content - bits of the brain as such do not have content, but instead a large part of the brain represents a great deal about how things are and should be might well object that what matters for them is not the history of bits of the brain or of particular implants, but instead the history of the brain as a whole. As a result, for them the history, or lack of it, of some particular implant or its input-output function is unimportant. They can, therefore, agree that patients should take a don't care attitude to the history of the implants. But these teleonomists cannot take a don't care attitude to a sequence of changes, and we can as easily make our point in terms of such a sequence. Suppose that aseries of operations is planned by a surgeon to replace someone's neurones because of a degenerative brain disease. At the end of the sequence, little or none of the original structure will be left. The patient, a good teleonomist, is assured that all will be fine, because the operations will be done with the right intentions, and, crucially, from a blueprint with the right causal history involving her mind-brain to ensure a derived function of the kind that confers content according to her version of teleonomy. Our teleonomist agrees, and the operation proceeds. But, we may suppose, a 'swamp' blueprint, a random aggregation of molecules which exactly resembles the real blueprint, materialises overnight on top of the real blueprint, and is accidentally picked up and used by the surgeon. How plausible is it that, after the sequence of operations is performed, the patient - or her family, perhaps convinced by teleonomists that she now believes and desires nothing - should insist that the operation be repeated using the original blueprint? It seems to us that it would absurd to ask for the operation to be done again; but then the teleonomist is committed to saying that content does not matter - just as we said before, and this time it does not help to deny the language of thought VI. We conclude by considering an interesting response that involves a big departure from usual versions of teleonomy. It might be urged that what really matters is that the input-output profile be of a kind

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson

489

Downloaded by [The University Of Melbourne Libraries] at 19:10 01 October 2013

with those with the right evolutionary history, even if the reason for the profile's presence in a given case has nothing to do with this history. This kind of teleonomy can w e l c o m e D o n a l d D a v i d s o n ' s S w a m p m a n into the c o m p a n y o f r e p r e s e n t o r s , for Swampman's input-output profile is of the kind which has evolved in the right way in humans? On this version, it might seem, there would be no reason for our patient or her family to ask for the operation to be done again, because the input-output profiles would be of a kind with those with the right histories. The trouble is that the input-output profile might have too many histories. There is no guarantee that a particular profile evolved only once, and if it evolved a number of times, there is no guarantee that on each occasion the same kind of history was behind it. 21 But then there would be no answer as to the content associated with the profile, as the kind it belonged to would have two quite different, putatively content-conferring histories. Moreover, and worse, this version of teleonomy suggests that what we think and want may depend crucially on how things are with creatures totally removed from us, both causally and in space and time. Whether or not an input-output profile is of a kind that has a certain history could be settled by the evolutionary histories of creatures in other solar systems, before the dinosaurs, after humans have died out, and so on. Suppose, to sharpen the point, that what matters according to the revised proposal is that there has already been a system which evolved to have a certain input-output profile. Moreover, there are two Swampmen: one early in the history of the universe, one late. Between them in time a species evolves with the same input-output profile as both. It seems arbitrary to suppose that the later Swampman gets to be a representational system but not the earlier one due to an accident of timing. On the other hand, if what matters is that at some point in history a system evolves to have the right profile, we get an even more unpalatable result. If a Swampman arises and there has not yet been an evolved system with the same profile, its representational status awaits what will happen in the possibly distant future? 2 University o f Auckland Australian National University Received December 1996 Revised April 1997

20 Donald Davidson, 'Knowing One's Own Mind', Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60 (1987) pp.441-458. 2, The same point applies mutatis mutandis to the suggestion that what really matters is that the neurological state be of a kind which has evolved in the right way in humans. 22 We are indebted to dissenting comments from Karen Neander, and to dissenting and supporting comments from referees.

You might also like