You are on page 1of 3

"Amartya Sen's Commitments"

Dan Little:
Amartya Sen's commitments, by Dan Little: A recent post examined the Akerlof and
Kranton formalization of identity within a rational choice framework. It is worth
considering how this approach compares with Amartya Sen's arguments about
"commitments" in "Rational Fools" (link).
Sen's essay is a critique of the theory of narrow economic rationality to the extent
that it is thought to realistically describe real human deliberative decision-making.
He chooses Edgeworth as a clear expositor of the narrow theory: "the first principle
of Economics is that every agent is actuated only by self interest" (Sen 317,
quoting Mathematical Psychics). Sen notes that real choices don't reflect the
maximizing logic associated with rational choice theory: "Choice may reflect a
compromise among a variety of considerations of which personal welfare may be
just one" (324). Here he argues for the importance of "commitments" in our
deliberations about reasons for action. Acting on the basis of commitment is
choosing to do something that leads to an outcome that we don't subjectively
prefer; it is acting in a way that reflects the fact that our actions are not solely
driven by egoistic choice. "Commitments" are other-regarding considerations that
come into the choices that individuals make.
Sen distinguishes between sympathy and commitment:
The former corresponds to the case in which the concern for others directly affects
one's own welfare. If the knowledge of torture of others makes you sick, it is a
case of sympathy; if it does not make you feel personally worse off, but you think
it is wrong and you are ready to do something to stop it, it is a case of
commitment. (326)
The characteristic of commitment with which I am most concerned here is the fact
that it drives a wedge between personal choice and personal welfare, and much of
traditional economic theory relies on the identity of the two. (329)
Sen thinks that John Harsanyi made an advance on the narrow conception of
rationality by introducing discussion of two separate preference orderings that are
motivational for real decision-makers: ethical preferences and subjective
preferences. (This is in "Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal
Comparisons of Utility".) But Sen rightly points out that this construction doesn't
give us a basis for choosing when the two orderings dictate incompatible choices.
Sen attempts to formalize the idea of a commitment as a second-order preference
ordering: a ranking of rankings. "We need to consider rankings of preference
rankings to express our moral judgments" (337).
Can one preference ordering do all these things? A person thus described may be
"rational" in the limited sense of revealing no inconsistencies in his choice
behavior, but if he has no use for these distinctions between quite different
concepts, he must be a bit of a fool. The purely economic man is indeed close to
being a social moron. Economic theory has been much preoccupied with this
rational fool decked in the glory of his one all-purpose preference ordering. To
make room for the different concepts related to his behavior we need a more
elaborate structure. (335-336)
Here is an example. "I wish I liked vegetarian foods more" is an example of a
second-order preference ranking: it indicates a rational preference for the first-
order ranking in which the vegetarian option comes ahead of the lamb option over
the ranking in which these options are reversed. And Sen's point is an important
one: the second-order ranking can be behaviorally influential. I may choose the
vegetarian option, not because I prefer it, but because I prefer the world
arrangement in which I go for the vegetarian option. Or in other words, one's
principles or commitments may trump one's first-order preferences.
Significantly, Sen's thinking on this subject was developed in part through a
conference organized by Stephen Krner on practical reason in the 1970s (Practical
Reason: Papers and Discussions). This is significant because it focuses attention on
a very basic fact: we don't yet have good theories of how a variety of
considerations -- ethical principles, personal identities, feelings of solidarity,
reasoning about fairness, and self-interest -- get aggregated into decisions in
particular choice circumstances.
Other economists might object to this formulation on the basis of the fact that
second-order preference rankings are more difficult to model; so we don't get
clean, simple mathematical representations of behavior if we introduce this
complication. Sen acknowledges this point:
Admitting behavior based on commitment would, of course have far- reaching
consequences on the nature of many economic models. I have tried to show why
this change is necessary and why the consequences may well be serious. Many
issues remain unresolved, including the empirical importance of commitment as a
part of behavior, which would vary, as I have argued, from field to field. I have
also indicated why the empirical evidence for this cannot be sought in the mere
observation of actual choices, and must involve other sources of information,
including introspection and discussion. (341-342)
But his reply is convincing. There are substantial parts of ordinary human activity
that don't make sense if we think of rationality as egoistic maximization of utility.
Collective action, group mobilization, religious sacrifice, telling the truth, and
working to the fullest extent of one's capabilities are all examples of activity
where narrow egoistic rationality would dictate different choices than those
ordinary individuals are observed to make. And yet ordinary individuals are
not irrationalwhen they behave this way. Rather, they are reflective and
deliberative, and they have reasons for their actions. So the theory of rationality
needs to have a way of representing this non-egoistic reasonableness. This isn't the
only way that moral and normative commitments can be incorporated into a theory
of rational deliberation; but it is one substantive attempt to do so, and is more
satisfactory (for me, anyway) than the construction offered by Akerlof and
Kranton.
(I also like the neo-Kantian approach taken by Tom Nagel in The Possibility of
Altruism as an effort to demonstrate that non-egoistic reasoning is rational.)

You might also like