You are on page 1of 21

Trustees of Boston University

Aristotle and the Irrational


Author(s): Thomas Gould
Source: Arion, Vol. 2, No. 2 (Summer, 1963), pp. 55-74
Published by: Trustees of Boston University
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20162836 .
Accessed: 20/09/2014 03:31
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Trustees of Boston University is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Arion.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

IRRATIONAL

THE

AND

ARISTOTLE
Thomas Gould

1 N ONE OF A SERIESOF LECTURES


in New York in 1912 he said:

deUvered

Gilbert Murray

which

Anyone who turns from the great writers of classical


Athens, say Sophocles or Aristotle, to those of the Christian
era must be conscious of a great difference in tone. There
is a change in the whole relation of the writer to the world
about him. The new qua?ty is not specifically Christian: it
is just as marked in the Gnostics and Mithras-worshippers
in JuUan and Plotinus
as in the Gospels and the Apocalypse,
as in Gregory and Jerome. It is hard to describe. It is a rise
in a sense, of pessimism; a loss
of asceticism, of mysticism,
of seff-confidence, of hope in this life and a faith in normal
human effort; a despair of patient inquiry, a cry for infaUible
an

revelation;

to the welfare

indifference

of

the

a con

state,

version of the soul of God. It is an atmosphere in which the


aim of the good man is not so much to Uve justly, to help
the society to which he belongs and enjoy the esteem of his
fellow creatures; but rather, by means of a burning faith, by
contempt for the world and its standards, by ecstasy, suf
to be granted pardon for his un
fering, and martyrdom,
his
immeasurable sins. There is an
unworthiness,
speakable
an increase of sen
intensifying of certain spiritual emotions;
a failure

sitiveness,

of nerve.

[Five Stages of Greek Religion


'The

failure

When
ourselves,

is, I suppose,

of nerve'

it is appUed by Murray
that

is,

at

a critical

originally

to a whole
moment

( 1925), p. 155]
taunt.

schoolboy's

civiUzation, however,
in

our

the

past,

phrase

to

takes on surprising dignity and seems full of meaning. Indeed, in


the years since 1912, in the dark days when it appeared as though
irrationaUty were finally taking over, that our civiUzation had lost,
once and for all, the strength and courage to face Ufe with rea
son and sanity, many a writer on both sides of the Atlantic found
himself reaching for Murray's phrase once again. But what ex
actly does the "failure of nerve" imply when it is used of the slow,
steady dissipation of rationaUty in the third and second centuries
B.C.? Just why did men?even men among the intel?gentsia, the
writers of books, setters of opinions, and leaders of society?turn
progressively away from rationaUty: away, that is, from the per
ception that it is not only possible, but all-important to figure
as well as one could? Why did they seem almost to
things out
want to forget that we must work continuously to see through
silUness,

what

prejudice,

and

irrational

passion,

and

to

aU of the alternatives might be, the probable

ask

ourselves

consequences

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

AND

ARISTOTLE

56
of
How

the
each,
are we

THE

standards

of

to

explain
overcome
with

frequently
even
to

to Uve

try

and

evidence
fact

the
the

rationaUy,

men

that

feeUng
that one

it was

that
must

so on?

and

verification,
more
were

and

more
sinful

somehow

and

power,

worship

fears and feelings of guilt to be the ulti

take nameless, mindless


mate

IRRATIONAL

truths?

Murray's

that

of nerve

failure

or

more

was

less

of the city state, at the establish

the collapse

is, of Alexander's

that

ment,

for

explanation

orthodox. After

men

empire,

could

no

orient

longer

themselves from their city walls, he argued. PoUtical power was


so far away that the ordinary citizen could no longer hope to
affect poUcies by argument or action; and distant decisions af
fected

his

own

as

life,

as not,

often

in economic

only

uncertain

ties, wars against peoples with whom he had no quarrel, or sud


den, inexpUcable uprootings and dispossessions. The old gods of
the city were exposed for what they were: empty and unable to
or comfort.

protect

Greek
taste

the

as a result

Then,

and oriental

civiUzations,
wines

bittersweet

of

of Alexander's

the men

the

to unite

efforts

of the West

East?those

to

began
and

personal

tional cults which are the chief export of Mesopotamia


Levant?and
they drank ever more greedily and deeply.

emo

and the

There is surely much truth in this analysis, but there are some
holes in it as well. For one thing, Chaldean astrology, magic,
cults

of

and

other

the Greeks

personal

salvation,
from

rites

of

Asia

and

the

great

phenomena
even before

ismore

age

ecstasy,
to
known

purification
through
were
Africa
well
of Pericles.

one wants

What

mar
insight into the spiritual decay which allowed these
to
and
Economic
of
Ufe
ginal ways
finally
approaching
triumph.
poUtical explanations are not sufficient. For another thing, the
centuries

immediately
not
merely

marked,

following
new
by these

the

of Alexander

conquests

allegiances

to dark

powers,

were
but

also by an ever more widespread devotion to a rather f ooUsh kind


of rationaUsm. Murray tended to exaggerate the sentimental and
religious sides of the Stoics and Epicureans. Taken all in all, thev
sense

in one

were,

of

the

more

word,

rational

than

Plato

and

Aristotle. For while the classical philosophers assumed that only


the rest
the gifted few could really live the life of reason?that
would have to borrow the necessary intelUgence from the laws
Stoics and Epicureans
and from the wisdom of their betters?the
offered systems which made the rational Ufe available almost im
even

mediately
peror

or

slave.

to
One

the most
feels

Umited
that

there

man
or woman,
person,
was
a failure
indeed
of

em
some

the
sort in the generation which saw the triumph of Macedonia,
death of Aristotle, and the foundation of the Stoics and Epicu
reans; but just what happened then, and why it took so long to
show its full effect, is far from clear.
Sooner

or

later

someone

was

bound

to offer

a Freudian

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

inter

Thomas Gould

for this failure of nerve. It was offered, in fact, by Mur

pretation

successor

ray's

57

at Oxford,

E.

R.

in a

Dodds,

series

of

lectures

which he deUvered in California in 1949. These lectures, which


he dedicated to Murray, were called The Greeks and the Irra
tional.1 Dodds traces with almost ghouUsh delight the slow spread
of

darkness:
in

belief
mortem

occultism,
and daemonic

mysteries,
evil
eye

the

the

punishment;

animals,

and

plants,

who would

savior?all

susceptible

'In all

as
poet
good
no mathematician

name

that

the

in philosophy

be

extinct?transcendental

for

this

would

it eventually

no

as

as Archimedes,

represent
he

decline,'

still

world would

scientist

good
and

it

made

succumbed,

of existence

centuries

awaiting

produce

no

as Eratosthenes,
. . . the one
great

a point of view believed


To

Platonism.

long-drawn-out

a mediator

and

the world

weakened

to which

sixteen

as Theocritus,
as
good

theurgy;
at
post
to certain

the initiate and his god; the hungry

he says, 'the Hellenic

it' (in 200 B.C.)

astrology,
terror

of magical
powers
the adoration
of

stones;

to the disease

Christianity.

possession;

attribution

precious

intercede between

for

look-out

alchemy,

says,

the

understand
'is one

to

reason

of the major

prob

lems of world history' (p. 244). Then, after warning his audience
modestly that the study of men's attitudes toward their irrational
experiences is only part of this larger problem, Dodds offers a
suggestion meant really to explain the whole decline of Greek
rationaUsm.
Dodds'

for

phrase

this

event

is nowhere

near

as

as Mur

good

ray's. In fact, he borrows a phrase from Erich Fromm, of all


people.2 It is 'the Fear of Freedom'. The idea which it repre
sents is more interesting: it might be summed up in the more
lurid phrase, 'The Revenge of the Id.' Dodds points out that the
really startling thing about the schools of philosophy which took
shape just after Aristotle's death is that they tended to deny the
existence

very

of

the

unconscious

those untamable

especially
conscious

personaUty

can

parts

of

the

human

and irrational energies


have

circumstantial

only

mind,

of which

the
but

evidence,

from which, unbeknownst to itself, it really draws all its fires. This
forgetfulness or suppression by the Hellenistic philosophers could
have been the thing which finally undid them, he argues, for, as
Freud

showed,

can

rationality

be

sustained

by

a man

only

so

long

as he remains alert to the


signs of these volatile and brutish drives
and

admits

ownership

to them

as a

part

of his

true

self.

If we

ex

amine the philosophies of the healthier period, Dodds points out,


we find a great contrast:
they were in full possession of this vital
insight.

Plato,

for

instance,

spoke

of

a monster

in us

all, whose

1
and Los Angeles,
1951.
2 Berkeley
See Dodds
(New York,
1941).
from Freedom
Escape
p. 252. The
in the lecture which
Freudian
Dodds
calls "The Fear
theory
implied
of Freedom,"
to the mixture
bears
little
resemblance
of
enough
Marxism
in Fromm's
and Romanticism
book.

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ARISTOTLE

58

AND

THE

IRRATIONAL

bestial and unholy appetites we are aware of reaUy only when we


are asleep; elsewhere he spoke of a terrifying black horse which
the driver of the soul can never hope entirely to understand or
subdue. Freud's term for this unconscious energy is the 'it,' 'das
Es' or, as it is usually translated in EngUsh (with an added sinis
ter sound not in Freud's German)
the id. He too pictures it in
one passage as a horse,3 although in his version we each ride our
horse rather than drive it from our chariot: the id, he says, is the
aUen brute which suppUes its rider with speed and energy, but is
capable also of throwing him and trampling him to death if its
power is forgotten for a minute. As the desires of the id are un
conscious, not only their nature but their very existence must be
inferred indirectly from dreams, sUps of tongue, thoughtless be
havior, and so on; and indeed, it was not until our own time
that a really tnistworthy technique was devised for unmasking
and examining this under-Ufe. But the founders of psychoanalysis
were always eager to point out that the great men of classical
and Plato above all?were
antiquity too?Sophocles,
Euripides
vividly and continuously aware of this counter-self. Indeed, sug
if these ancients had not had this amazing self
gests Dodds,
their brilUant rationalism could not have lasted for
knowledge,
a

day.

Now it is a cardinal tenet of psychoanalytic


theory that you
cannot reaUy reason with the id; in order to Uve a rational Ufe
allow
you must
in your
wants,

the monster
dreams,

some

fantasies,

sort

of

in aU

satisfaction
and

day-dreams,

its

thousand

inexpUcable rituals, large and small, pubUc and private,


and unconscious,
all through your Ufe. If you refuse
can do
to
its
demands?a
recognize
altogether
thing which you
your attention from the evi
only by deUberately withdrawing
dence for its existence?it will simply take over: hysteria, insanity,
otherwise
conscious

paralysis,

uncontroUable

despair,

obsessions?its

revenge

has many

forms. For the id, it seems, harbors two strident and dictatorial
drives, both of which, unless heavily disguised, are utterly ab
horrent to the conscious self: it has a Umitless appetite for camal
a
gratification, and will to destroy?to destroy something outside
itself if it is aUowed the chance, to destroy itself if it is not. It is
no
incapable of responding directly to reason, because it knows
law outside itself, not even the laws of cause and effect. Nor does
it have so much as a sense of time. UnUke our conscious selves it
never rests, night or day. We can relax in sleep, notice, only by
inventing dreams which fool the id, making it think that it is
getting what it wants.
(Luckily it does not know the difference
between an image and a fact. ) But we must fool ourselves at the
same time. If the disguise becomes too thin, allowing our con
scious
3New

selves

to

recognize

Introductory

Lectures

(London, 1957), p. 102.

the monster

what
on

Psychoanalysis,

reaUy

wants,

Tr. W.

we
J. H.

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

wake
Sprott

Thomas Gould

59

up instantly, in a cold sweat. And if a man is not allowed to sleep


at all, or even to day-dream, for several days and nights in a row,
a
collapse of the conscious Will follows with horrible inevita
to
in the East have discovered
biUty?as certain governments
their deUght. The id takes over and rational judgement is no
we all lay ourselves open to this kind
longer possible. But in fact,
of catastrophe whenever we fail to keep alert to the signs of the
beast

clamoring

within

we

whenever

ourselves,

its

deny

exist

ence or underestimate
its power. Consider then, Dodds suggests,
if our whole civiUzation did not make precisely
this mistake
end
the
B.C.
somewhere
about
the
of
fourth
century
beginning
Are not the phenomena of the following centuries classic symp
toms of the revenge of the id?We denied altogether the existence
of the irrational within us, and so eventuaUy we were deprived of
the strength to Uve the Ufe of free, rational individuals.
This thesis is controversial, of course (to say the least!). But it
deserves very careful consideration. Now the basic theory is not
the chief difficulty, I think. Indeed, Dodds has chosen one of the
most successful of Freud's ideas. In fact, since the triumph of
in the 1920's, many forms of hysterical breakdowns
psychoanalysis
have all but disappeared among the educated. We are too aware
of our unconscious now to let things get to that state: we sUp
into

various

neuroses

boring

In

instead.

other

Freud's

words,

theory about the revenge of the id has been verified by the fact
that it has effected a change in the phenomena. Not that HoUy
wood has heard about this yet, to be sure. They continue to show
us "Freudian" thrillers where hysterical
paralysis is inevitably
as

explained

we

the

result

of

are actually beyond

sider

this

one

item:

under

personaUty

stress,

childhood

shell-shock,
so common

the

complete
in the First

virtually unknown in the Second World War.


Nor does the trouble Ue in the assumption
vidual

may

suffer,

and

"traumas,"

the

Uke.

But

that now, thanks to Freud himself. Con

a whole

civiUzation

may

collapse
World
War,

that what

suffer

also.

of

the
was

an indi

That

is an

idea which has proved brilUantly illuminating, from Plato's Re


public to Freud's Totem and Taboo. Rather, what we must do
now, in the wake of Dodd's suggestion, is to re-examine antiquity
itself, and see how far the idea may need to be modified if it is to
seems to be mainly
explain the facts. Dodds
right about the
Stoics, for instance, that they denied the existence of an incor
rigibly irrational element within the human psyche, but it ap
pears

that

the

Stoics

were

by

no means

unanimous

in this

assump

tion, as he admits. And Dodds seems to be right only in a very


queer sense when he Usts Aristotle along with Plato as one of
those of the great healthy period of rationaUsm who had a
deep
respect for the unquenchable power of the irrational.
This is a point of considerable
interest, because if Aristotle

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

AND

ARISTOTLE

60

THE

IRRATIONAL

really was the last to respect the id, then we will still be able to
assume that the fatal mistake coincided with the traditional date
for the end of classical Greece?the
beginning of the "Hellenistic"
period, the generation, that is, which was just getting under way
when Aristotle died. If, on the other hand, Aristotle turns out to
have denied the reality of the irrational, then we must look for the
error farther back, at least as far as the period of Aristotle's youth
and Plato's old age, and perhaps farther back yet, to the heyday
of classical Athens.
Did Aristotle accept the existence of the id or not? It would seem
that one would only have to look at the texts and find out. It is
not so simple, however. If you collect together all of Aristotle's
on

remarks

madness,

ritual

melancholy,

cures,

dreams,

tragic

pleasures and wild music; his visions of god and cosmic beauty,
individual failure and poUtical stupidity; his analyses of action
under
of war,

stress,
evil

or sexual

drunkenness

anger,
rhetoric,

his

passion;

and

poetry

slavery,

acceptance
to

melodies;

upsetting

say nothing of his detailed theories of mutilations and monstrous


find that he is almost always acute, sensitive and
births?you
about

intelUgent

factor

this

of

comes

One

reality.

from

away

Jeanne Croissant's Aristote et les Myst?res


(Li?ge, 1932) with
the feeUng that Aristotle was deeply impressed with the ubiquity
contrast to his master Plato, who
of irrationaUty in the world?in
lashed out with rage or spat with disgust at people who could not
obUterate irrationaUty from their Uves.
On the other hand, if you collect Aristotle's careful analyses of
the metaphysical
and
emotions;
causation
and

status

of

more

when

even
in

general,

that Aristotle

covery

in Plato's

motion

and human
chance,
luck,
look at his treatment
of nature
you
cannot
be
struck
the dis
but
by

necessity,
you

simply

leaves no place

for truly irrational

undirected

sense?absolutely

working

toward no genuine

universe,
sense
of

to Aristotle,
is
actually
according
at
the word?aimed
unerringly

energy

energy,

in the

All motion

good whatever.

rational
some

real

in

the

strict

advantage

however often conflicts between such aims may result in failure,


waste, or tragedy in this or that part of the sublunary world.
That is, a lamb headed straight for all that a lamb should be
a
a
might get in the way of wolf headed straight for all that wolf
from the shepherd's
should be. The result will be unfortunate
point of view (to say nothing of the lamb's). But there is nothing
irrational here, it is all expUcable by the identification of the
several genuine goods being pursued, the perfection of lambhood
and

the

whole,
for

the

irrational,

of wolfhood.

perfection

And

anyhow,

the death of a lamb is an inconceivably


so-called
not

irrational
in the

that their tendencies

sense

within
passions
are
that they

men's
aimless,

in the universe

as a

trivial event. As
are
they
psyches,
in the sense
but

are simple and unambiguous?like

the wolf's,

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Thomas Gould
or

a rock when

like

like

as

tree

it hurtles
ever

it grows

toward

the

closer

to

center
a

of

or

the universe,

its

of

specimen

perfect

61

kind. When Aristotle zeroes in on the most basic of all of his


differences from Plato, it is precisely this feature which he hits
on: whereas Plato had thought that there must be a source of
undirected,

unpredictable,

in

energy

unanalysable

universe

the

preventing the visible world from attaining perfection, he, Aris


totle, saw for the first time that one needed no such hypothesis.
And surely this squares well with our general impressions of
both Plato and Aristotle. When Aristotle discusses
irrational
it

phenomena,

is

to

always

that

show

are

they

not

irra

really

tional, that there is no true difference between these and rational


phenomena. And when Plato tells us that all irrationality is bad by
definition, it is because he has a healthy respect for its undying
the impossibiUty of reconciling it with
power, and understands
true

is Plato,

It

rationality.

not

who

Aristotle,

has

us

given

so

many unforgettable
pictures of the undersides of our psychic
before, he speaks elo
energy. In the Republic, as I mentioned
in
vision
id
of
the
his
the
of
quently
many-headed monster which
comes aUve at
some apparently good
night in the dreams even of
and happy men, and in the Phaedrus he Ukens the id to an ugly,
vicious black horse quite capable of wrecking the chariot of our
soul. The desires of this black horse are an obscene parody of our
reasonable

it is a permanent

but

aims;

of us,

part

Plato

argues,

so

we had
just better get used to it and learn how to render as harm
less as possible its hideous tendencies and appetites. In the world
as a whole,

too,

unpredictable
encies

Plato

even

which

the

toward

tending
beauty,
or indeed

universe

essentially

or Chance?tend
could

not

reduce

around you: you see that things are

patterns

perfect

the

of

and

wild

he calls Necessity

designer

to his plans. Look

entirely

is a similar

there

says,

energy, which

and

splendor?whether
colors,
orders,
powers,

everywhere?toward
strength,
trees or men,
think
of horses,
of every
excellences
dimensions,

you

sort; but you also see that all of the horses, all of the trees, and
all of

the men

exists

no

waste

more

and

are maimed
than

pure

unhappiness

or another,
in one way
and pure water
or the
Confusion,
purely
equal.
or lesser
to a
abso
reign
greater
degree
blue

the possible exception of the outer


lutely everywhere, with
heavens. If there is energy toward perfect patterns, then, there is
also another kind of energy?energy
toward no goals whatever,
planless

motion,

"wandering"

as

Plato

says,

incapable

of

being

harnassed entirely for the purposes of intelligence. Plato was


against the id. (If intelligence is the best possible move toward
how could one defend wnintelUgence?)
But
genuine well-being,
to be against the irrational is hardly the same as to fail to under
stand it.
One

can

and find,

read many,

really, very

many

pages

in Aristotle,

little appreciation

on

the other

hand,

of the irrationaUty of

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

62

ARISTOTLE

AND

THE

IRRATIONAL

irrational phenomena. The element of Necessity which so haunted


cosmos is defined out of existence by Aristotle.
Plato's would-be
It has two main senses: the inevitable push of a piece of matter
toward the perfection of some species, or the unwanted interrup
tion in such a process caused by the interference from another
(as in the case
piece of matter on the way toward its perfection
of the lamb and the wolf.)4 Or, of course, you can speak of
in a "hypothetical" sense: if the lamb is to reach the
Necessity
full glory of its species, it will need to find in its pasturage the
foUowing proportions of the various species of crude elements,
so on.5

and

But

as a source

Necessity

of unruly

motion,

a fountain

head of failure, ugUness, and corruption, he specificaUy denies.6


As for Chance, that is not a real cause either, it is justwhat we say
when two or more purposive processes yield as an incidental side
effect an event which some person or natural tendency might have
aimed at, although none did. In reaUty, all motion and process in
the whole of the universe is purposive, however true it may also
be that the criss-cross of various processes down here beneath
the moon never aUows any single being to reach absolute per
fection, even for a minute. After all, in addition to the rather
wasteful interactions between individual plants and animals (not
too wasteful, though, Aristotle thought) there is also an inevitable
frustration resulting from the fact that higher patterns of perfec
not by pure matter
like men?are
realized,
organisms
more
matter
by
by
elementary
pre-formed
already
so on. Even
and
water,
however,
here,
flesh,
grain,
a
acts
Uke
Aristotle
economical
housewife,
marvelously

tion?complex
directly,
patterns:
nature

but

points out,7 often utiUzing the apparently waste materials with


wonderful
ingenuity.
The patterns of perfection being striven for by matter are
reduced by Aristotle to the species of plants and animals, and
their parts, also the various kinds of crude elements (these are
distinguished by the place in the universe at which they would
come to rest?their tendencies toward the center or the periph
men are driven to super
ery), and finally, the patterns which
or
on
their
impose
surroundings, artifacts, buildings, poUtical
so
on.
In
and
each
addition,
health,
ganizations,
speeches, plays,
of the heavenly spheres has a beauty which is being realized in its
perfect

circular

and

motion,

round and round by desire

the

as

universe

for the most

a whole

is moved

of all things,

beautiful

4
See, e.g. Eudemian Ethics II 1224 a 15 ff. and b 10 ff., also
Posterior Analytics II 95 a 1 ff., and De partibus animalium I 639 b
25 ff.
5 See

Physics

especiaUy

II ch.

9,

and

duction ? la Physique Aristot?licienne2


6
Metaphysics

ch.

9, Cf.

ch.

10, N

cf. Augustine

Mansion,

Intro

(Paris, 1946) 282-289.


ch.

4,

De anima III 430 b 22.


7De
generatione animalium II744 b 16 ff.

and

Physics

I ch.

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

9. Cf.

Thomas Gould

63

God. Now Aristotle claims that if you could discern all of these
patterns, from the lowliest to the most august, you would have a
complete explanation for every single thing that happens in the
whole universe. This is because the only other thing in nature,
matter, has neither resistance nor any independent energy of its
own, only love and desire for the perfection of these patterns,
nothing else. As he puts it in the clearest of the several passages
(Physics I, ch. 9) where he contrasts his analysis of nature with
the one which he learned from his teacher, while Plato thought
that matter simultaneously
cooperated with and frustrated the
realization

the patterns,

of

saw

Aristotle

was

that matter

motivated

only by desire for these patterns. What failure there was could
all be traced to the effect of mutually exclusive patterns pulling
the same substratum. And the frustrations are trivial, Aristotle
thought, in comparison with the glorious order of the whole
(Metaphysics A ch. 10).
All of this, all that I have said so far about Aristotle's vision of
the universe, is reasonably clear and for the most part, quite
is all there in Aristotle's writings, and accurate
uncontroversial?it
wiU
be
in any decent study of Aristotle's system.
found
analyses
And yet you will also find it said, in handbook after handbook,
after monograph,
that there are really two processes
monograph
at work

in

(sometimes

sometimes

cooperation,

at

cross-purposes)

in all natural events?that


in addition to the pull of the perfect
patterns you also have other tendencies latent in matter itself.8
Now it is true that when Aristotle describes individual events,
of an individual specimen of
especially the coming-into-being
some species of
plant or animal, he does, quite often, speak of
or

irregularity

resistance

in

the

stuff

itself,

it from

preventing

a perfect
becoming
example of its kind;9 but in the passages
where he broadens his scope and discusses with rigid precision
the true nature of aU of the factors involved in a natural event,
Aristotle leaves no possible explanation for this apparent resist
8
Eduard
E.g.
B. F. C. CosteUoe

and
ZeUer, Aristotle
and J. H. Muirhead

the

465, ff.; J. L. Stocks, Aristolelianism


Robin,

Aristote

(Paris,

1944)

Earlier

(London,

tr.

Peripatetics,
I 355,
1897)

ff.

by
and

(London, 1925) 45-57; L?on

15&-158;

Mansion,

cit.

op.

289-90;

H. H. Joachim, Aristotle: The Nicomachean Ethics (Oxford, 1951)


184; D. J. Allan, The Philosophy of Aristotle (Oxford, 1952) 47-8;
Friedrich Solmsen, Aristotle's System of the Physical World (Ithaca,
1960)

104-5.

The

only

exceptions

seem

to be

the

discussions

of

Physics I ch. 9 and the like which merely accept Aristotle's analysis of

matter

e.g. W.

without
D.

Ross'

or not he was
whether
questioning
always
of the Physics,
edition
and Harold
Cherniss,

Criticism of Plato and the Academy


9
be

E.g.
two

Final
20-24.

consistent,
Aristotle's

(Baltimore, 1944) 90.

I 642 a 1, ff. where


animalium
there are said to
partibus
later as the Material
and
causes,
(identified
cause)
Necessity
Causation.
et corruptione
also De
C.f.
II 336 b
generatione
See the passages
cited by Mansion,
28-30.
op. cit. 289, notes
De

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

AND

ARISTOTLE

64

ance of matter

THE

IRRATIONAL

were

but that the other patterns which

at a more
the matter
elementary
pulling
as crude
fied
tissues,
elements,
organs,

already

level?the

patterns
so on?were
not

and

identi
pull

ing the matter into just those realizations which would be re


quired if the new, unifying pattern were to be perfectly reaUzed.
What we must remember is that there simply is no such thing as
entirely
out

matter?one

unpatterned
we

of water,

would

orate?to

that

behave,
Da

Leonardo

is,

according

Vinci's

as

that matter
to

paintings

out

the

pattern

such

resisted

of water

or a wall.

If

is not

that

brown,

turning

of

a house

to flow and evap

of a foundation

are

not

house,

tried to build

of this bit of matter

the construction

preclude

If we

not

discover,

us, but that the tendency


would

makes

or bricks.

but out of wood

matter,

because matter has a tendency to undo his designs, but because


the particular matter which Leonardo chose tended toward pat
terns which were incompatible with his higher plans for them.
The very same thing happens in conception and digestion, Aris
totle suggests. The only difference really is that in the appropria
of matter

tion
the

for

structure

of

natural

constructions,
raw materials
are

the

of an artist or artisan

beyond the wildest nightmares


anima 1403 b 11-14).
can

how

Now,

we

notion

that Aristotle

failure

in the

art? Well,
careless

writing;

to make

quite
But

"irrational."
Indeed,

he

of

persistence

(cf. De
erroneous

this

as such to be the cause of

believed matter

striven
and
for in nature
patterns
own
can
Aristotle's
blame
certainly
in
not
take
the pains
he does
always
particular,
or
he means
"matter"
clear
the words
just how

realization

for

the

explain

about
specifications
a
with
preciseness

the
dictated

one

then

regularly

the

of

thing,

we

is never

Aristotle
a

asks

great

deal

a
writer.
considerate
very
of his readers,
that
namely

they keep the whole of his immensely complex analysis of reaUty


vividly before them at all times. But there is a much more impor
tant

reason

for

this

universal

almost

and

misunderstanding,

that

is

the gross improbabiUty of Aristotle's idea itself?the very sugges


tion itself that the whole world could be shown to be really
look
flawlessly rational if we but looked closely enough. We
around

us

and

we

see

that

these

we

patterns

should

Uke

nature,

and we

seem to strive for patterns;

be

unable

ourselves,

indeed

does

reaUze that if it were not for


to make

any

sense

of

our

perceptions of separate experiences and make predictions which


will be vaUd for the future; but we also see, as Plato taught us
to do,
perceive
for our

that
with

eyes
tions?similarities

these

patterns
our minds,
us
give
only
but no

are

never

not

our

an

actually
eyes, where

infinite

identities

reaUzed.

sequence
our
among

We
are

things
of unique
experiences

have

to

tending,
percep
in this

some kind of
perpetual flux. Surely, we say, this points clearly to
an irreducible brutishness and irrationaUty in the very stuff of the
world: how, we ask, could Aristotle possibly have avoided that

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Thomas Gould

65

conclusion?
In

we

fact,

question,
we
man,

Indeed

we

is what

this

own Uves are full of


ugliness
and
in

a man

and

emptiness,
dream.

as

And

we

are

feel,

must

who

Hobbes'

famous

by

phrase,

could

be

It might
to

than
aware

constantly

as of the orderly
Our

"reaUstic."

being

triviality, absurdity

see

not

with

this, we

capital

is

say,

"N,"

well,

Uving
how

If even a man's Ufe is usually,

could that be anything but worse?


to use

be

as well

mean

does

well
to Plato

closer

and hardships,

nature

for

as we

far

rational universe.

aspects of our world

of the appalling
aspects.

as

vision of a completely

on this
that,
a sensible
For

be
argued
Aristotle.

in a way,

are,

today

from Aristotle's

nasty,

"solitary,

and

brutish

short,"

how much less satisfying yet, we feel, must be the brief survival,
say, of a hen, a rat, a weed, a piece of mud or a drop of Uquid?
We could not bring ourselves to take seriously any philosopher
who denied that. Our vision of natural processes has been per
in his films of wild-Ufe: some un
fectly stated by Walt Disney
beUevably hideous rodent, insect, or reptile is forever being shown
an
enemy in long, slow, ugly gulps.
eating
equally unedifying
Our sciences all tell the same tale: physics, medicine,
psy
chology, anthropology?all
catalogue the weird array of unin
telligent drives which we take to be the real world. In fact, we are
always faintly embarrassed to find traces of intelligence, beauty
or

even

excellence,

within

ourselves.

Aristotle

that

suggested

the

pull of rational goals on the mind of an intelligent man has an


exact counterpart in the pull which the patterns of nature exert on
matter; we are far more struck by the thought that probably our
conscious
ful

plans
the spin

than

and

are
no more
designs
really
our brains
electrons
of which

rational

of

the

meaning
are made.

If we do look for something in nature which mirrors our own


souls, we find it quickly enough, but it is not the orderUness, it is
the
nize

planless
as

and

destructive
to

counterparts

tendencies
the

we

which

stupidity,

vulgarity,

blind self-gratification which we know all about within


Now

we

notice,

some

with

ourselves.
a level

was

that Aristotle

satisfaction,

recog
and

instantly
violence,

headed

scientific in his spirit.


chap, realistic and downright
Further, we notice that, far from denying the existence of the
waste and failure everywhere which so impresses us, he
spends
many pages describing it, often in painful detail. And so we are
simply baffled and greatly disappointed when we come to the
accounts which Aristotle gives
grossly inadequate metaphysical
of

these

brute

tendencies.

How,

we

ask,

can

one

man

describe

so well and yet


deny the existence of irrational energy
altogether? And so, instead of taking a closer look at his descrip

nature
tion

of

natural

physics. We
any

real

actually

drives,

conclude

status
to

to

describe

we

tend

to

turn

our

that, despite Aristotle's

genuinely
purposeless
a human
or natural

on

backs

his

meta

odd failure to allow

energy,
event,

when
he

he
must

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

came
have

AND

ARISTOTLE

66

THE

IRRATIONAL

slipped again and again into the inevitable


as

that matter
was

true

the

such,
author

by
of

and

sluggishness

all

Platonic

of

"To what

imperfection.

assumption

aimlessness

its own,

other

source,

indeed," says Eduard Zeller,10 "could this be traced?"


But the truth is that Aristotle apparently did not see it that
that the source of
way. He tells us repeatedly and consistently
or

violence

in

resistance

realization

the

of

be

should

pattern

traced, not to energy or sluggishness in the stuff of the world as


such, but to other patterns also pulling the same piece of matter.11
since

And

means

rationaUty

action

aimed

at a

accurately

genuine

all of these patterns are causes of motion precisely


good?and
because they are good, the goals which motivate both men and
nature?true
not

at no
aimed
energy
the universe,
according

irrationaUty,
in

exist

anywhere

does

genuine
good,
to Aristotle.

He

really did deny the reaUty of the irrational, the id, in all of nature
and therefore, a fortiori, inman. The temptation is then very great
to throw up our hands and assume that surely Aristotle could not
in
have kept this clearly in mind throughout his meticulous
of the whole of the universe; but let us resist that
vestigations
make

and

temptation

visuaUze what
existence

of

as

instead

an

brave

famines,
quakes,
and death. Well,

the large, obvious


wars,

diseases,

storms, earth

things:

of pain
inevitabiUty
to
in
these
things
keep
this
sort, you will
notice,
the

murder,
you have

Aristotle,
and
failures

says
conflicts

perspective:

of

actually occur only in that fraction of the universe which


sphere
inevitable

eternity.

to

the

irrationaUty.

Let us begin with

the moon.

of

the

can

as we

effort

look like to a man who denied

the world would

and
stops
turns
the
God

motion

rectilinear

where

Beyond,
starts
is

unknown,
totally
outermost
he
sphere,

is below
its

with

and
beauty
contact
is in direct
all

is

only with

that, and the farther you get away from him, the more

confusion

you must
the master

household,

But

expect.
must

be

as
then,
in efficient

in any well-run
command
every

or

state
minute

of the day and night, but the lowliest servants can be allowed to
waste a good deal of their Uves just kilUng time (Metaphysics A
ch. 10). And the system works remarkably well, really. The sun
moves north and south every year with a perfect rhythm; and this
creates

seasonal
mixtures

cruder

the

That
thing.
its pattern
onto

his

sperm?and

10
Op.
11 The

here
when

to survive
the

of matter?an

separates

cause

in turn

which

is, the parent,


on to a
piece

it off

proper
oak
from

the patterns

eternally
season
onto
himself.

it is to be a full grown oak or what

then?what
grown,
matter

changes,
down

happy
from
cit.

man?pulls
its environment,

at

shaping
every

despite
arrives,
its acorn,
The

stamps
a man
pattern,

it is to be a full

the matter,
appropriate
utiUzing
is reached
and
until maturity

new
it is

357.

relevant

passages

are

collected

by

Cherniss,

loe.

cit.

above).

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

(n.

Thomas Gould
time
survival

on
to pass
its pattern
again.
is
of the
species
guaranteed

In

this

eternal

the

manner,
if sooner

even

or

67

some

later

thing inevitably destroys the pattern of each individual speci


men (De generatione et corruptione II ch. 10). Indeed, so beau
tifully arranged is the whole, that the variety of the species which
are

in this manner

to survive

able

forms

or chain,

ladder

perfect

are left out


from the lowest to the highest kind possible?none
De
IV
VIII
588
b
animalium
animalium
4-16,
(Historia
partibus
681a 12-16). So you see, when that wolf prevented the lamb from
a sheep, nothing
achieving the full splendor of what it is to be
very
important happened.
really
As

for

nature's
an

produce

inevitable

individual

errors

little

specimen

every

some

of

it

time

species,

to

tries

is not

too

that

is
really very hard to explain, Aristotle thought.12 Conception
to
in
human
he
creative
the
the
arts,
process
precisely parallel
points out: the pattern is realized by being superimposed, as it
onto

were,

the matter

matter,

foreign

as

selected

being

already

suitably formed on a more elemental level. Error obviously is


possible at either of two points; either the matter itself is not
(as in the case of the man trying to build a
suitably pre-formed
house out of water) or the active striving toward the new pattern
is it, Aristotle
is itself somehow distracted by other goals. Why
muses,13 that the young of wild animals look very like their par
ents, but the young of human beings often do not? Could it be, he
concentrate

that
animals
suggests,
sometimes
men's
minds
on

the

the woman's

pattern;

a 11).

if the man

Now

while
passes
was
to

patterned matter

of differently

I 729

animalium

generatione

they
copulate
who
notice,
Aristotle
job,
thought,

only

the original mixture

supply

when

It is the man,

wander?

does

(De

his

part

well, if other goals do not divide his energy at the crucial mo


ment, the foetus will be male and will strive, not only for the
pattern "what it is to be a full-grown and happy man," but will
strive also toward re-producing all of the little peculiarities which
made

the

father

unique?the

father into baldness,


pattern

Aristotle
The

most

is not

done

outlines
common,

is the female

frustrating

which

side-goals

drew

the

irrascibility and so on. If the stamping of the

well,
he

various

however,

and classifies
says,

and

he
peculiar
phenomenon
ness,"?"natural"
because,

calls

the most

animalium

(De generatione
an

although

things

these accidents
interesting

may

happen.

in grisly detail.
monstrosity

IV 775 a 16). This

a "natural
lame
ava-n-qpla ^vo-lkt]
a botched
is indeed
the woman

attempt at realizing the pattern Man (after all, male and female
cannot be two species of the genus Man, because they do not
each reproduce their own kind), nevertheless nature does utilize
12Most

114, ff.
13

but

of

the

relevant

passages

are

X 10, written
Problemata
perhaps
in its
orthodox
entirely
implications,

collected
one
by
I think.

by Mansion,
of Aristotle's

op.

cit.

students,

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ARISTOTLE

68

this waste
ing

IRRATIONAL

in a most

product
the next

again

THE

AND

time

in the process
way
then another
whole

ingenious
And

around.

of
class

try
of

monstrosities,
giants, dwarfs, and the like, follow inevitably from
in
which the matter presented by the female is pre
conceptions
formed by patterns other than the most congenial ones. But in all
fairness to nature, it must be said that it really does amazingly
well: look around you and you will see an astonishing number of
really good attempts at reaUzing that intricate pattern known as
In fact, Aristotle points out (Nicomachean Ethics II
Manhood.
1106 b 14-15), nature, which pursues its patterns without con
or deliberation

sciousness
are

beings

in that

is

really much
and
completion

imitation

better

than

we

we

of nature

human
art.14

call

But this brings us to the most crucial point of all in our project
to picture the world as harboring no truly irrational tendencies.
How are we to account for all of these foolish lusts, passions,
fears, hungers, and distracting emotions which are always leading
you and me into stupid, ruinous decisions? If all of the activities
in the whole universe are caused by the single-minded
love of
matter for the perfection of these patterns, whether it be a stone
a
falUng off cliff, a plant unfurling its leaves, or a beast pursuing
its prey, what in the name of heaven is a man doing when he finds
it advisable to go against an involuntary or instinctive drive
within him? Is man, by reason of his intelUgence, the only irra
in the universe?
That would
indeed
be an odd conclu
thing
But consider
for a minute.
It is a fact, after
all, as Zuckerman
err in sexual
rats never
matters
that whereas
showed,15
(isolate
tional
sion.

them from birth, then put them together, a male with a female,
and they will know exactly what to do), an ape, because of his
superior intelUgence, has to be taught by his elders in these
matters. And as for human beings?the
difficulties which they
in
trying
known.

discover
too well

sense

to make
"Congenital

of

their

relations

sexual

ignorance,"

are

Aldous

concludes

all

Hux

ley, is apparently "the condition of intelligence." But does that


mean that the more intelUgent an animal is, the more Ukely it is
to make
reason
14

mistakes?
means

Protrepticus

fr.

abiUty

15 See

Aldous

to act

13, Physics

1337 a 2, Meteorol?gica
Works

in one

Yes,
the

Huxley,

but
sense,
in more
II ch.

is

that

really
only because
one
And
this
way.16

than

8, also

194

a 21-2,

Politics

VII

Iv 381 b 6-7.
Texts

and

Pretexts,

vol.

17

in the Collected

(London, 1949) 137 f.

16
6 ch.
2 and 5. As
for Aristotle's
1-5,
Metaphysics
especially
at
de
and very
absolute
attempts
avoiding
peculiar
unsatisfactory
in nature
E
19 a 6-b
terminism
4, Metaphysics
(De
interpretatione
et corruptione
II ch. 11, De partibus
ch. 3 and K ch. 8, De generatione
a 8-10.
1-5
I
animalium
III ch.
and
640
Ethics
Nicomachean
+
Die
des
also H. Maier,
ch. 3), see Mansion,
op. cit. 315-333,
Syllogistik

Aristoteles
Nicomachean

(T?bingen, 1896) I 83, ff., H. H. Joachim, Aristotle, The


Ethics

(Oxford,

1955)

Newman, The Politics of Aristotle

108-11,

also

22-6,

and W.

(Oxford, 1887) I 16-24.

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

L.

Thomas Gould

69

in turn is a good thing to have, for it follows that there must be


more than a
main pattern
single drive toward the reaUzation of the
in question. For instance: the rock never errs in hurtUng toward
the center of the earth (throw it upward ten thousand times,
Aristotle points out, and you will never even begin to pervert it
from its true instincts [Nicomachean Ethics II ch. 1] ), but if it is
one inch from the edge of a cliff it is powerless to further its
course

over?it

by moving

tireless

futility

to press
on

continue

will

move

and

nowhere.

Plants,

downward
the

with

other

hand,

a hill, turn their leaves


push aside dirt, correct for the slope of
toward the sun?all sorts of things. But a plant is powerless to
defend itself against a goat if one should choose to chew off all
of its bark. The goat, by contrast, is well able to defend itself
its enemies,

from

attacks

against

say

from

fox?it

hungry

can

run away. But to stop chewing bark and to consider what


fight or
be
done to prepare for future fox raids is quite beyond the
might
powers of the goat. Man, on the other hand, can do just that: lay
aside his interest in present satisfaction and look ahead to remoter
means that
contingencies. Thus to have intelligence, although it
one

ever

makes

so

far greater

with

pattern

more

many

the abiUty to perceive

also means

mistakes,

and pursue
than

precision

that

to the

is open

one

has

of a complex

the perfection

unintelligent.

But this still leaves unanswered the excruciating problem of the


status of those instincts and desires which
the
metaphysical
man must squelch or resist. In the battle between fear
prudent
and

or

reason,

lust

between

and

for

reason,

instance,

is

what

are fear and lust,


really going on? Why, on Aristotle's analysis,
not just as rational as reason? We cannot allow him to make this
one
or

in the whole

exception
to

experience

is, by a genuine
that

fox. Here

sion when

pleasure

good?as

is our

it vetoes

ghastly
a natural

thing in the universe!


slips

out

of

our

universe.
must

just

desire

goods,

but

we

save

our

are

skin
that

the fall of that stone or the anger of


a rational
deci
again:
to be the one
irrational

once

paradox
desire

seems

more.

All

passions,

indeed rational, in the strict sense, caused,

genuine

to

as rational-motivated,

But we have not caught Aristotle


once

net

The

be

never

in fact

he

yet; he

suggests,

are

that is, by the pull of

presented

with

one

soli

tary drive within us which we must frustrate for our own higher
benefit: we are invariably presented with two, mutually exclusive,
passions of this sort, and the intelligent decision is to take that
course between them which is aimed most economically
toward
our
the true realization of the pattern Man?toward
highest pos
in
in other words. True, if a man is wanting
sible happiness,
and
has
been
he
will
have
exercised
perception
badly trained,
one of the pair of
conflicting passions to the point where it is far
too strong for him to battle against; but there was theoretically a
time in his Ufe when itwas still possible for him to avoid this state
of affairs (Nicomachean Ethics III ch. 5). The fact that a man

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

THE

AND

ARISTOTLE

70

IRRATIONAL

can eventually find himself with an


incorrigible character, a state
where he can no longer feel clearly the pull of his truest good, is
no more

Aristotle

surprising,

case

is the

suggests,

than

efficient

course

the man

of

who could have thrown a stone a minute ago but finds that that is
no longer in his power now that he has
dropped the stone out of
his hand. However
little we may be aware of the fact in daily
life, especially after we have been corrupted by bad habits, the
truth is that regrettable desires invariably pull on us in mutually
exclusive

our most

and

pairs,

lies between

always

two.

the

This

infamous, much

tendency

ridiculed

the mean

to take

path

I think,

as a

accounted

for,

incredibly

difficult metaphysical

his

to make

to

for

say,

the

of

It cannot be
to

problem

real

all

one

surely

attempt

desperate

resulting
True,

irrationaUty.

seem

Even
when
plausible.
a desire
simultaneous
with

an

solve

in finding psychological

ingenious

theory
that

instance,

is

blunders.

problem?a
away

explain

is marvellously

Aristotle
ments

to

attempt

except

as a

excellence

extremes

to explain of all of Aristotle's

the hardest

from

theory of moral

between

argu
is forced

he

to flee

from

battle, we also invariably feel a desire to run head-long into fire


(Nicomachean Ethics II ch. 7 and III ch. 6-9), he manages to
touch upon something which may well be true. In addition, he
finds that the theory fits tolerably well with some others of his
ideas, and even with ideas latent in Plato's teachings.17 It remains
a bizarre

herent

charge of harboring
In

there

fact,

is indicative

and

however,
theory,
in Aristotle's
main

of

to clear

program:

in

the

difficulty
universe
of

the

any

irrational impulses.

are

quite

number

famous

of

philosophical

puzzles, I would maintain, which can be solved only if we take


seriously this insistence by Aristotle that true irrationality has no
real

existence.

For

there

example,

is

the

curious

that

fact

Ari

stotle, who did not have a poetic atom in his body, should have
been the one to defend the rationality of poetry and tragic drama,
whereas Plato, one of the great poets of all time, had found it
necessary to lash out in terror at the power which poetry and
could

tragedy

wield

over men's

minds.

Let us look at this strange development. Poets and dramatists,


Plato pointed out, are imitators. That is, they show the outsides
of things: how men walk, talk, show fear, delight, and so on.
What poets do not do is go, Uke philosophers,
directly to the
heart of things and explain what is really going on. But alas, says
can
a clever
Plato,
poet
that his audience,
deeply

derstood
poet

or

2, ff.,

seem

moved,

something marvellously
the

language;
17 Cf.

also

audience

could

but that discovery

X 619
Republic
a 27, ff., 431
III426

articulate

so
convincing
assumes
that

profound.
the

new

in his

imitations

it must

Not

have

that either

insight

un

the

in rational

is only taken as proof of the Umi

a ff., the Philebus


De
passim,
a 11-20,
VII ch. 3.
Physics

anima

II 424

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Thomas Gould
tations
the

of

rational

far more

surely

The

language.
of our own

man

literate

in

wisdom

literate

man

felt

that

time,
great

of Plato's
art

like

time,
there

somehow

imaginative

71

was

in rational

than

investigations. But this was a feeling which Plato wanted to fight.


It is not only good poetry and drama, Plato pointed out, which
sweeps men along and gives them this sense that they are getting
extraordinary insights. Men find different things profound accord
ing to the wisdom which they bring with them into the theater.
of
And what is worst of all, the real secret of the persuasiveness
music
is
its
that
and
draw
their
excite
myth
tragedy
compelling
ment entirely from the release which they give to the dangerous
irrational tendencies dammed up within our psyches. The trouble
with learning from poetry, then, is that one has to be a philoso
pher first before he can tell which poems are wise and which are
not.

judgment of history has gone against Plato

The
but

so much

not

because

his

was

analysis

in this matter,
or unsound,

unfeeling

I think, as because philosophy never again reached the standard


for rational discourse which Plato set for it. On the other hand,
Aristotle's

drama

see how

that worked.

and

human

as rational

poetry

human
the

world,

and

been

immeasurably

forced him to

are

therefore

the only differ

in
is that
energy
in the matter
there

right

us

Let

good.

out before,

non-human

patterns

has

and

system, as I pointed

In Aristotle's
between

times

that his metaphysics

by the odd chance

reinstate

ence

in modern

reputation

enhanced

non

the

which

they are pulling?as the pattern of the full-grown oak must be there
acorn from within?while
in human actions the pattern
pulling the
is in some

mind,

person's

him

drawing

on

to

the

reproduce

pat

tern in matter which he finds lying at hand (Physics II ch. i).


Indeed, when a doctor brings into being the pattern Health, not
in another

in his

but

body,

art

his

own,

is

a natural

like

precisely

process. Now when a man is motivated


by the belief that he
should bring into being some pattern which he sees in his mind
a house,

say

a constitution

speech,

it?

not,

Certainly

the pattern Man


7-8).

One

of

Aristotle,

says

or
more

any

over

system

after all, is that all of the patterns which

the mind

nature

at

and

art may

be

to

assumed

embedded

right there in matter,

permanent

nevertheless,

propagation
pattern

simply

that

hends

exist

to another

house

a housebuilder

the principle

see

in

exactly

any

the

built

they

by

in

moment

to be
eternal

by

can hardly pass on its

same

and the advantages,

perceives

given

survive

way

in his son. Presumably


a house

Z ch.
Plato's,

else, and yet

nowhere

because

of their kind. Still, a house

keeps his pattern going

to

invents

(Metaphysics

of Aristotle's

advantages

a father

than

in the act of conception

the

are we

play?how

in his mind? Did he invent

of that pattern

explain the appearance

another

a man

in which

what
man,

happens

is

compre

and is led to build

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

72

AND

ARISTOTLE

THE

IRRATIONAL

house for himself


(cf. De partibus animalium I 639 b 17, ff.).
Or perhaps in backward times, he sees the requisite pattern im
pUed in nature. (Think how much Greek architecture resembles
a forest.) Aristotle did believe that the arts
progressed and de
cUned, that they found full realization in one generation and
were but dimly perceived
in others;18 nevertheless,
he insisted
that no pattern can have been invented ex nihilo, either in nature
or in human activities, or they would not be eternal and there
fore not universals and objects of knowledge. Therefore the pat
tern House,

also

the

pattern

must

Tragedy,

existed

have

forever,

?
passed on from one reaUzation to another (cf. Metaphysics
1047 a 2?of the art of housebuilding).
But tragic drama presented a very special problem, for two
reasons.

First,

was

Aristotle

all

aware

too well

that

were

tragedies

a recent and local taste. Second, Plato had trained his


biggest
guns on tragedy and shown with horrible clarity how destruc
tively irrational it could be. Thus Aristotle had to demonstrate,
first, that the pattern which, when well reaUzed, was caUed
Tragedy had really been around all the time, and, secondly, that
it was as rational as any of the other activities and institutions in
it was not an
which men habitually engaged themselves?that
evil, in other words, but a good.
solution shows wit and cleverness. He picks up
Aristotle's
Plato's very words and makes them work for his theory. Plato said
drama

that

was

imitation.

Very

then,

well,

says Aristotle,

that wiU

work admirably as a way to identify the eternal activity which is


expressed in writing and attending dramas. Children, notice, do
not have to be taught to imitate; it seems to be a natural need.
Then if we assume that epic poetry is but a less effective mani
festation of the same eternal pattern (Poetics 1459 a 5 ff.), we
can trace a gradual progress in the perception as to how this
pattern

is best

reaUzed.

When

men

wrote

epics

in the

dim

past,

they were pursuing the pattern which moderns reaUze better in


plays, Aristotle suggests. But what is the good in this pattern,
what is it that draws men to reproduce it as men are drawn to
reproduce the pattern House or Health? Plato directed our at
tention to the manner in which drama rouses us to disturbing
emotions of pity and fear (Republic X 606). Very well, then, let
us take our cue from the way in which the arousal of violent
emotions has a purifying effect in many an ecstatic ritual (cf.
Politics VIII ch. 7). Why may we not assume that the arousal of
pity and fear has just this effect on us in the theater? Finally
Plato said that drama imitated the actions of men (ibid. 603) ;but
we

can

answer

that

an

imitation

of

highly reveaUng, and even philosophic


essential

beauty?in

other

words,

it

an

action

can

be

selective,

in that it displays order and


completes

the

tendencies

18Politics VII 1329 b 24,


ff., also II 1264 a 3, ff., Metaphysics
1074 b 10, ff. and Laws III 676.

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

of

Thomas Gould
Nature

and

plays,

reveals

our

case

and

voil?,

prove

the
a

by
we

eternal

careful

have

reinstated

Poetry is rational?imagine
trying to prove that!

of

let us

Now

themselves!

patterns
examination

the most

effective

as a rational

poetry

73

activity.

to

being driven by your metaphysics

Well, there it is: the world as it looked to a man who denied the
reality of genuine irrationaUty. If Aristotle had not also been a
very great genius, the whole project would have been irritating,
even monstrous. But I suppose we should be
glad that somebody
tried it. Or should we? According
to Dodds' version of the
Freudian

it was

theory,

precisely

our

because

once

civiUzation

tried to argue that the irrational did not exist, that irrationality
finally took over and reigned for centuries. If Aristotle was the
first to show how we might systematically ignore all evidence of
the id, then, according to Dodds' argument, he may have been
one of the chief authors of the downfall of ancient rationaUsm.
Or was Aristotle just a child of his generation, as we say?Was he
perhaps just the cleverest of many people who were thinking
along those lines at that time? Still, the guilt would seem to be
very great on the head of the first man to show just how the
of

suppression

our

awareness

of

true

was

irrationality

consonant

with progress in every department of science and art.


But what are we to make of this larger theory?that a whole
civiUzation loses its abiUty to hang on to reaUty whenever
it
suppresses all memory of the existence of the id? There is a new
book inspired by Dodds as much as by Freud himself, which
tries to explain the insanity of the French Revolution, coming as
it did

at die

example

of

end

of

same

the

an

reason

of

age

phenomenon.19

and
Perhaps,

hard-won

enlightenment,
this
then,

as

an

pattern?

rationaUty, followed by super-rationaUty denying all


irrationaUty, followed by the triumph of irrationality?is repeated

at many
generations,
exciting
remember

at

levels

and
discovery
that

same

the
whole

individual
time, within
civilizations.
But
let us

to cause
the

age

us
of

to

the

over-simplify

enlightenment

was

lives, nations,
not
allow
this
must

facts. We
also

the

age

of

Blake and Swedenborg; the age of Freud cUmaxed in the Second


World War. And right in the heyday of ancient rationaUsm we
find, not only Aristotle, but Socrates too, in a way, and perhaps
also some of the Sophists, arguing the id right out of existence.
Dodds closes his lectures with the pious hope that we today,
armed as we are with the new vision given us by
psychoanalysis,
will

never

suffer

so violent

a withdrawal

from

reasonableness

as

our fathers did at the end of


antiquity (op. cit. pp. 254-5). But
this raises a doubt from another quarter. When we
classify and
explain our every irrational drive, are we not doing just what
19Brigid Brophy, Black Ship To Hell (London, 1962) 279, ff. and
359.

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

ARISTOTLE

74

did?

Aristotle
not

really
to
addition
is

else

AND

THE

IRRATIONAL

not

that,
saying
are
if
they

we

Are

irrational

at

all

our
confessing
ownership
contrast
of us: we must
required

over

your
it as no

cepted
versal

law

irrationality
but

anomaly
Is our
of nature?

to

such

the

with

if, like Aristotle,


an inevitable
scientific

you

just

expression

investigation

of

calmly
of the

us

once

more

is Plato's
way:
pose,
remain
essentially
dence
that it exists,

to Aristotle's
recognize

fatal
that

error?
the

incomprehensible;
that it is immortal,

truly

ac
uni

alternative,
must
irrational

circumstantial
accept
and that it is your

lead
I sup

The

always
evi
enemy;

tap it cautiously in symbols and in song; and hate it with


love of life which you have in you!

20 It is true

you

irrationality,

by making us doubt that there is such a thing as rationality,


ing

are

drives

In
correctly?20
id, then,
something
it our rational
selves

kind of a victory would

and honor this above the id.What


have

in a sense,
understood

was

all the

a convinced
to his
duaUst
dying
day, and
meant
the fact that to be irrational
to be
in note
the lecture
cited
above
3, especially
incomprehensible
(e.g.
awareness
this vivid
is meant
to be
of what
) ; but one meets
pp. 98-99
in his followers.
truly irrational
only very infrequently
that

he

often

that Freud

emphasized

This content downloaded from 192.167.204.6 on Sat, 20 Sep 2014 03:31:32 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like