You are on page 1of 13

AI Magazine Volume 3 Number 4 (1982) ( AAAI)

Why People Think


Computers Cant
Marvin Minsky
MIT
Cambridge, Massachusetts

MOST PEOPLE ARE CONVINCED computers cannot think. ever really think. I think those specialists are too used t,o
That is, really think. Everyone knows that computers al- explaining that theres nothing inside computers but little
ready do many things that no person could do without electric currents. This leads them to believe that there cant
thinking. But when computers do such things, most people be room left for anything else-like minds, or selves. And
suspect, that there is only an illusion of thoughtful behavior, there are many other reasons why so many experts still main-
and that the machine tain that machines can never be creative, intuitive, or emo-
. doesnt, know what its doing tional, and will never really think, believe, or understand
. is only doing what its programmer told it to anything. This essay explains why they are wrong
. has no feelings. And so on.
The people who built the first computers were engineers Can Computers Do Only What Theyre Told?
concerned with huge numerical computations: thats why
the things were called computers. So, when computers We naturally admire our Einsteins and Beethovens,
first appeared, their designers regarded them as nothing but and wonder if computers ever could create such wondrous
machines for doing mindless calculations. theories or symphonies. Most people think that creativity
Yet even then a fringe of people envisioned whats now requires some mysterious gift that simply cannot bc ex-
called Artificial Intelligence-or AI for short-because plained. If so, then no computer can create- since, clearly,
they realized that computers could manipulate not only num- anything machines can do can be explained.
bers but also symbols. That meant that computers should be To see whats wrong with that, wed better turn aside
able to go beyond arithmetic, perhaps to imitate the informa- from those outstanding works our cuhure views as very best
Con processes that happen inside minds. In the early 1950s, of all. Otherwise well fall into a silly trap. For, until we
Turing began a Chess program, Oettinger wrote a learning first have some good ideas of how WC do the ordinary things
program, Kirsch and Selfridge wrote vision programs, all us- -how ordinary people write ordinary symphonies-we simply
ing the machines that were designed just for arithmetic. cant expect to understand how great composers write great
Today, surrounded by so many automatic machines, in- symphonies! And obviously, until we have some good ideas
dustrial robots, and the R2-D2s of Star Wars movies, most about that, wed simply have no way to guess how difficult
people think AI is much more advanced than it is. But still, might be the problems in composing those most outstanding
many computer experts dont believe that machines will works-and t,hen, with no idea at all of how theyre made,

THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982 3


of course theyll seem myst,erious! (hs Arthur Clarke has TRY; you need not, know which one actually will work. Even
said, any technology sufficiently advanced seems like magic.) earlier, in 1956, Ncwcll, Shaw, and Simon developed a com-
So first wed better understand how people and computers puter program that was good at finding proofs of theorems
might do the ordinary things that we all do. (Besides, those in mathematica.1 logic-problems that college st,udents found
skeptics should be made to realize t,hat their argumentIs imply quite hard-and it even found some proofs that were rathe
that ordinary people cant think, either.) So lets ask if we novel (It also showed that computers could do logical
can make computers that can use ordinary common sense; reasoning- but this was no surprise, and since then weve
unt,il we get a grip on that we hardly can expect to ask good found even more powerful ways to make machines do such
questions about works of genius. things.) Later, Ill discuss how this rclxtes to the problem of
In a practical sense, computers already do much more making programs that, can do common-sense reasoning.
than their programmers tell them to. Ill grant that the car- Now, you might reply, Well, everyone knows that if you
liest and simplest programs were little more than simple lists try enough different thlpgs a.t random, of course, event,ually,
and loops of commands like Do thzs. Do that. Do thas and you can do anything. But if it takes a million billion trillion
that and thzs agazn until that happens That made it hard years, like those monkeys hit,ting random typewriter keys,
to imagine how more could emerge from such programs than thats not intelligence at, all. That,s just Evolution or some-
their programmers envisioned. But t!heres a big difference thing.
bct,ween impossible and hard to imagine. The first is Thats quite correct- except that the GPS system ha.tl
about at; the second is about ?JOU! a real difference - it didnt do things randomly To use it,
Most people still write programs in languages like BASIC: you also had to add anot,her kind of knowledge ~~advicc?
and FORTRAN, which make you write in tha.t style-lets about when one problem-state is likely to be better than
call it do now programming This forces you to imagine another Then, instead of wandering around a.t random, the
all the details of how your program will move from one state program can seek the better sta.tes; it sort of feels a.round,
to anot,her, from one moment to the next,. And once youre the way youd climb a hill, in the dark, by always moving up
used to thinking that way, it is hard to see how a program the slope This makes its search seem not random at all,
could do anything its programmer didnt think of- hccause but rather purposeful The trouble~and its very seriou-
it, is so hard to make that kind of program do anythzng very is that it can get stuck on a little peak, and never make it
interesting. Hard, not impossible. to the real summit, of the mountain.
Then AT researchers developed new kinds of program- Since then, much AI research has been aimed at finding
ming. For example, the General Problem Solver system of more global ways to solve problems, to get a.round that
Newell, Shaw and Simon lets you describe processes in terms problem of getting stuck on little peaks which are bettel
of statements like if youre on the wrong side of a door, go than all the nearby spots, but worse than places that cant,
through it-or, more t,echnically, if the difference between be rcachcd without descending in between Weve discovered
what you have and what you want, is of kind I>, then try to a variety of ways t,o do this, by making programs take
change that difference by using method M.l Lets call this larger views, plan further ahead, reformulate problems, use
do whenever programming. Such programs automatica.lly analogies, and so forth. No one has discovered a completely
apply each rule whenever it,s applicable-so the programmer general way to always find the very highest peak Well,
doesnt have to anticipa.te when that might happen. When t,hat,s too bad~bllt it, doesnt, mean t,hcres any diffcrcncc
you writ,e in this style, you still have to say what should here between men and machines--since people, too, are al-
happen in each state the process gets into-but you dont most always stuck on local peaks of every kind Thats life
have to know in advance when each state will occur Today, most AI researchers use languages like LISP, that,
You also could do such things with the early program- let a programmer USC general recursion. Such languages
ming language CjOMIT, developed by Yngve at MIT, and the are even more expressive than do whenever languages, be-
SNOBOL la.nguage that followed it Today, that progra.m- ca.use their programmers dont have to foresee clearly either
ming style is called production systems.2 The mathemati- the kinds of states that might occur or when they will oc-
cal theory of such languages is explained in my book. cur; the program just constrains how states and st,ructures
will rclat,c t,o one another. We could call these const,raint,
That General Problem Solver program of Newell and languages
Simon was also a landmark in research on Artificial Intel- Even with such powerful tools, were still just, beginning
ligence, because it showed how to write a program t,o solve to make progra.ms that, can learn and can reason by analogy
a problem that the programmer doesnt know how to solve. Were just starting to make systems that will learn to recog-
The t,rick is t,o tell the program what kinds of things to nize which old cxpcriences in memory are most analogous to
present problems. I like to think of this as do something

Of course, Im greatly simplifying that history


4This isnt quite true LISP (loesnt really have those rlo whenevels
Allen Newell and Herbert Simon, Human Problem Solmng
built into it, hut, programmers can learn t,o make such rxt,ensions, and
Marvin Minsky, Computatron: Finite and Injinzte Machines, Predce- most AI workers feel that, t.he ext.ra flexibility out.weighs the incon-
IIall 1967 vcnicncc

4 THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982


sensible programming. Such a program would remember a but in order to acquzre such a combina.tion, you need at least
lot about its past so that, for each new problem, it would a lucky accident-and maybe something else-to make you
search for methods like the ones that worked best on similar able, in the first place, to acquire those other skills.
problems in the past When speaking about programs t,hat I dont see any mystery about that mysterious comhina-
have that much self-direction, it makes no sense at all to tion itself. There must be an intense concern with some
say computers do only what theyre told to do, because domain. There must, be great proficiency in that domain
now the programmer knows so little of what situations the (albeit not in any articulate, academic sense) And one must,
ma.chine may encounter in its future-or what, it will remem- have enough self-confidence, immunity to peer pressure, to
ber from its past. break the grip of standard paradigms. Without that one
A generation later, we should be experimenting on pro- might solve problems just as hard-but in domains that
grams that write better programs to replace themselves. Then wouldnt be called creative by ones peers. But none of
at last it will be clear how foolish was our first idea-that those seems to demand a basic qualitative difference. AS
never, by their nature, could machines create new things. 1 see it, any ordinary person who can understand an ordi-
This essay tries to explain why so many people have guessed nary conversation must have alrea.dy in his head most of
so wrongly about such things. the mental power that our greatest thinkers have In other
words, I claim that ordinary, common sense alrea.dy in-
cludes the things it takes-when better balanced and more
Could Computers Be Creative?
fiercely motivated-to make a genius. Then what makes
t,hose first-raters so much better at their work? Perhaps two
I plan 1,o answer no by showing that theres no such
kinds of difference-in-degree from ordinary minds. One is
thing as (creativity in the first place. I dont believe theres
the way such people learn so many more and deeper skills
any substantial difference between ordinary thought and
The other is the way they learn to manage using what
creative thought. Then why do we think theres a difference?
they learn. Perhaps beneath the surface of their surer mas-
Ill argue that this is really not a ma.tter of whats in the
tery, creative people also have some special administrative
mind of the artist-but of whats in the mind of the critic;
skills that better knit their surface skills together. A good
the less one understands an artists mind the more creat,ive
composer, for example, has to master many skills of phrase
seems the work the artist does.
and theme-but those abilities are shared, to some degree, by
I dont blame anyone for not being able to do the things
everyone who talks coherently. An artist also has to mastel
creative people do. I dont blame them for not being a.ble
larger forms of form-but such skills, too, are shared by
to explain it, either. (1 dont even blame them for thinking
everyone who knows good ways to tell a tale. A lot of
that if creativity cant be explained, it cant be mechanized;
people learn a lot of different skills-but few combine them
in fact I agree with that ) Hut, I do blame them for thinking
well enough to reach that fronta. rank One minor artist
that, just because they cant explain it themselves, then no
masters fine detail but not the larger forms; another has the
one ever could imagine how creativit,y works. After all, if you
forms but lacks technique.
cant understand or imagine how something might be done
We still dont know why those creative masters learn
at all, you certainly shouldnt expect to be able to imagine
so much so well. The simplest hypothesis is that theyve
how a machine could do it,!
come across some better way to choose how and what to
What, is the origin of all those skeptical beliefs? Ill
learn! What might the secret be? The simplest explanation:
argue first tha.t were unduly intimidated by admiration of
such a gift is just some higher-order kind of expertise-
our Bcet,hovens and Einsteins. Consider first how hard WC
of knowing how to gain and use ones other skills What
find it to express the ways we get our new ideas-not just
might it take to learn that? Obvious: one must leurn to be
creative ones but everyday ideas. The trouble is, when
better at learnzng!
focllssing on creativity, were prone to notice it when others
If thats not, obvious, perhaps our culture doesnt teach
get ideas tha.t we dont. But, when we get our own ideas,
how to think about learning We tend to think of learning
we take them for granted, and dont ask where we get
as something that just happens to us, like a sponge getting
them from Actually we know as little-maybe less-of how
soaked But learning really is a growing mass of skills; we
we think of ordinary things. Were simply so accustomed
start with some but have to learn the rest Most people
to t,he marvels of everyday thought tha.t we never wonder-
never get deeply concerned with acquiring increasingly more
until unusual performances attract attention. (Of course,
advanced learning skills Why not? Recause they dont pa,y
our superstitions about creativity g+cvc other needs, e.g., to
off right away! When a child t,rics to spoon sand into a pail,
give our heroes special qualities that justify the things we
ordinary losers cannot do.)
Should wc suppose that outstanding minds are any 50f course each culture s&s a threshold to award t.o just, a few that
rank of first class creativity-however great 01 small t,he difIelenccs
difrerent from ordinary minds at all, except in matters of de-
among contestants This must. make social sense, providing smallish
gree? Ill argue both ways. Ill first say No, theres nothing clubs of ideal-setting idols, but shouldnt then burden our philosophy
special in a genius, but just some rare, unlikely combination with talk of inexplicability There must, be better ways t,o deal with
of virtues~ -none very special by itself. Then, Ill say Yes, feelings of regret at being second-1 ate

THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982 5


the child is mostly concerned with filling pails and things time. Really, its usually much easier to think of good prob-
like that. Suppose, though, by some accident, a child got lems than to solve them-though sometimes it is profoundly
interested in how that pail-filling activity itself improved over hard to find exactly the right question to ask. In any case,
time, and how the minds inner dispositions affected that a culture frames its history of ideas so that the rewards are
improvement. If only once a child became involved (even largest for opening new areas. But the problems znside each
unconsciously) in how to learn better, then that could lead subject can be just as hard.
to exponential learning growth. The reason this speculation is wrong is that, in order to
Each better way to learn to learn would lead to better solve any really hard problem (by definition of hard), one
ways to build more skills-until that little difference had has to find a way to break it down into other problems that,
magnified itself into an awesome, qualitative change. In this one can solve. Therefore, the ability to invent and formulate
view, first-rank creativity could be just the consequence new problems must already be a part of being reasonably
of childhood accidents in which a persons learning gets to intelligent. It only obscures the point to argue that those are
be a little more self-applied than usual. 6 If this image only sub-problems. The ability to compose good questions
is correct, then we might see creativity happen in machines, is a requisite of intelligence, not a special sine qua non for
once we begin to travel down the road of making machines creativity.
that learn-and learn to learn better. Besides, some people, more than others, prefer to look
Then why is genius so rare? Well, first of all, the question outside a present context and ask larger questions like Am I
might be inessential, because the tail of every distribution working on the right problem? But everyone can do this to
must be small by definition. But in the case of self-directed some degree-and can be worse off by doing it excessively.
human thought-improvement, it may well be that, all of us I see nothing especially mysterious about that inclination to
are already close to some edge of safety in some socio- take a larger view.7 The interesting problem is less in what,
biological sense. Perhaps its really relatively easy for certain generates the originality, and more in how we build control
genes to change our brains to make them focus even more on mechanisms that appropriately exploit and suppress it.
learning better ways to learn. But quantity is not the same The rest of this essay explains the weaknesses of several
as quality-and, possibly, no culture could survive in which other common theories of how machines must differ fun-
each different person finds some wildly different, better way damentally from minds. Those theories are unproved today-
to think! It might be true, and rather sad, if there were not because of anything about machines, but just because we
genes for genius that werent hard at all for Evolution to know too little about how human minds really work. Were
come upon-but needed (instead of nurturing) a frequent, simply not prepared to search for things that we can do but
thorough weeding out, to help us keep our balance on some machines cannot. Because of this, well focus on a more con-
larger social scale. structive kind of question: why people are so very bad at
making theories of what they can or cannot do!

Can Computers Choose Their Own Problems?


Can Computers Think Only Logically?
Some people even ask How could computers make mis-
takes? as though, somehow, ability to err itself might be
Our culture is addicted to images of minds divided into
some precious gift. Theres nothing wrong with seeking for
two parts. Usually, one mind-half is seen as calculating,
some precious quality, but only some form of quiet despera-
logical, and pretty brittle; the other half seems sort, of soft
tion would lead one to seek for it in error and mistake.
and vague. There are so many variants of this, and all so
It seems to stem from the misconception that creativity is
ill-defined, that its impossible to tell them apart: lets call
rooted in some chance or random element that cant be
them Soft-Hard Dumbbell theories:
found in any well-defined machine. This is silly, first because
machines can simulate random behavior as well as one can Logic - Intuition
want, and, second because it doesnt explain the consistency Spatial - Verbal
and coherency with which creative people produce. Quantitative ~ Qualitative
Another often-heard speculation: I can see how a Local ~ Global
machine could solve very difficult problems that are given to Reason - Emotion
it by someone. But isnt, the very hardest and most import,ant Thinking ~ Feeling
Literal - Metaphorical, etc.
problem, really, to figure out what problem to solve? Per-
haps the thing machines cant do is to invent their own prob-
Theres nothing wrong with starting with two-part, the-
lems? This is wonderfully profound and silly at the same
ories-if you use them as steps toward better theories. But

6Notice, that theres no way a parent could notice-and then reward-


a young childs reflective concern with learning. If anything, the kid 7That is, given the advanced abilities to plan, generalize, and make
would seem to be doing less rather than more- and might be urged to abstractions that all ordinary people possess; computers havent ex-
snap out of it hibited much ability in these areas, yet

6 THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982


when you stop at dumbbell thcorics then, most likely, you Those age-old distinctions between Logic and Intuition,
have only one idea instead of two: or Reason and Emotion, have been the source of many un-
sound argumentIs about machine intelligence. It was clear
Whatever-it-is-~ ~Everything else.
in AIs earliest days that logical deduction would be easy
The trouble with one-part theories is that they dont lead to program. Accordingly, people who imagined thinking tlo
anywhere, because they cant support enough detail. Most bc mostly logical expected computers soon to do the things
of our cultures mental-pair distinctions arc stuck just so, that people used their logic for. In that view, it ought to be
which handicaps our efforts to make theories of the mind. much harder, perhaps impossible, to program more qualita-
Im especially annoyed with recent fads that see minds as tive traits like intuition, metaphor, aesthetics or reasoning
divided evenly into two halves that live within t,he left and by analogy. I never liked such arguments.
right-hand sides of the brain: In 1964, my student T.G. Evans finished a program
to show that computers could actually use ana.logies. It
LEFT-LIKE-RIGHT-LIKE
did some interesting kinds of reasoning about perception of
(Computer-like)-(Rest-of-mind-like)
geometric structures. This made some humanistic skeptics
This is really neat. It not only supports beliefs that so angry that they wrote papers about it Some threw out
minds do things computers cant, but even provides a handy the baby with the bath by seeming to argue that if machines
physical brain-location in which to put the differences! could indeed do that kind of analogical reasoning, then,
Each half of the brain has dozens, and probably hundreds maybe that kind of reasoning cant be so important One
of different sections of machinery. There definitely are of them complained that, Evans progra.m was too compli-
some differences bet,ween right and left. But these struc- cated to be t,he basis of an interesting psychological theory,
tural differences between corresponding parts of the right because it used about 60,000 computer instruction-words
and left halves appear very much less than the differences (That seemed like saying there wasnt any baby in the first
wzthin each half. Despite that flood of half-baked brain-half place.)
st,ories, Ive heard of little evidence for systematic differences In any case Evans program certainly showed it was
in how those left-right portions really function, in spite of all wrong to assume computers could do only logical or quan-
those newsstand magazines and books, and it would seems tit,ative reasoning. Why did so many people make that mis-
that even brain-scientists theories about minds arc just as take? I see it as a funny irony: those critics had mistaken
naive as yours and mine. Theyre just, as prone to observe thezr own personal limztations for limitations of computers!
whatever distinctions t,hey imagine. ,Just for fun, Ill con- They had projected their own inability to explain how eit,her
tribute two of my own speculations on what our brain-halves person or machine could reason by analogy onto the outer
do: world, to suppose that no well-defined mechanism could do
such a thing. In effect, they were saying that since they could
MASTER-SLAVE THEORY: The two brain-sides at first
see no explanation then, surely, there could he no explana-
develop more or less the same ways, in parallel. As time
goes on and specialties mature, the need for order and
tion!
coherency requires one to become dominant: a program Another misconception stems from confusing different
cannot, smoothly serve two mast,ers Whichever side ac- senses of logic. Too many computer specialists talk as t,hough
quires control, perhaps according t,o some inborn bias, computers are perfectly logical, and thats all. What they
the other side remains more childish and subservient, really mean is tha.t they can understand, using logic, how all
and used for cruder, simpler parts of whatever computa- those tiny little computer circuits work But, just because
tion is involved the little circuits can he understood by logic doesnt mean at
DIFFERENCE THEORY: Our AI t,heories of thinking em- all that those circuits can only do logic! Thats like thinking
phasize mechanisms for recognizing differences This re- you could figure out what houses are for from knowing how
quires access to closely relat,ed pairs of descriptions. One bricks work.
must describe the present situation as it is; the other Many AI workers have continued to pursue the use of
describes the ideal or goal-that is, the situation as one logic to solve problems. This hasnt, worked very well, in my
wishes it to be. What better way to do that than to
opinion; logical reasoning is more appropriate for displaiing
slave together a pair of similar machines with, say, one
or confirming the results of thinking than for the thinking
side depicting more of whats perceived, the other rep-
itself. That is, 1 suspect we use it less for solving problems
resenting anticipated or imagined goals
than we use it for explaining the solutions to other people
Either image seems to suit those popular but, va.gue and-much more important- to ourselves When working
descriptions of the two dissect,ed personalities, right and with the actual details of problems, it is usua.lly too hard to
left, that emerge when surgeons split a patients brain in package the knowledge we need into suitablly logical form
halves. The right side, say, would be better at realistic, con- So then we have to use other methods, anywayPmethods
crete things-things as they are. The left half would ha,ve more suitable for the networks of meanings that Ill dis-
spccializcd in long-range plans, in things that arent yet, in cuss shortly. Still, I consider such ideas to be of great impor-
short, at things we like to call abstract. tance in making theories of how we represent the things we

THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982 7


think about, and especially in how we think when we reason what is good, without considering each persons different,
carefully. hopes and fears.
Fortunately, as I will show, t,here isnt any need t,o try
to capture meanings in such rigid, public ways. In fact.,
Could a Computer Really Understand Anything?
that would defeat our real purposes. This is because any
I see youve programmed that computer to obey verbal psychologically realistic theory of meanings needs built-in
commands. Youve probably inserted into its memory ways to deal with individual differences between the people
how it, should respond to each command But I dont who are to do the knowing
believe the program really understands the words, in any
human sense.
Could A Computer Know What Something Means?
This criticism is deserved by most computer systems
around these days. But how does it apply to the 1965 pro- We cant think very well about meaning without, think-
gram written by Daniel Bobrow that solves high-school al- ing about the meaning of something. So lets discuss what.
gebra. word problems?? It could solve some problems like numbers mean. And we cant think about what numbers
these: mean very well without thinking about what some particular
The distance from New York to Los Angeles is 3000 number means. Take Five Now, no one would claim that
miles. If the average speed of a jet plane is 600 miles Bobrows algebra program could be said to understand what,
per hour, find the time it takes to travel from New York numbers really are, or even wha.t Five really is. It ob-
to Los Angeles by jet viously knows something of arithmetic, in the sense that it,
can find sums like 5 plus 7 is 12. The question is-does it,
Bills fathers uncle is twice as old as Bills father Two
understand numbers in any other sense-say, what are 5 OI
years from now Bills father will be three times as old as
Bill The sum of their ages is 92 Find Bills age. 7 or 12-or, for that matter, what are plus or is? Well,
what would you say if I asked, What is Five? Ill argue
Most human students find problems like these quite hard. that the secret lies in that lit,t,le word other.
They find it easier to learn t,o solve the kinds of eq?Lations Early this century, the philosophers Russell and White-
they encounter in high school algebra; thats just cook-book head suggested a new way to define a number. Five, they
stuff. But to solve the word problems, you have to figure said, is the set of all possible sets with jive members This
out what equations to solve. Doesnt this mean you have set includes every set of Five ball-point pens, and every litter
to understand at least something of what the words and of Five kittens. The trouble was, this definition threatened
sentences mean? also to inchide sets like these Five words and even the
Well, to begin with, Bobrows program used a lot of Five things that youd least, expect Sets like those led t,o so
tricks. It guesses that the word is usually means equals. many curious inconsistencies and paradoxes that the theory
It doesnt even try to figure out what Bills fathers uncle is, had to be doctored so that these could not be expressed-and
except to notice that this phrase resembles Bills father. that made the theory, in its final form, too complicated foi
It doesnt know that, age and old have anything t,o do any practical use (except for formalizing mat,hematics, where
with time, only that theyre numbers to bc put into, or it worked very well indeed). But, in my view, it offers little
found from, equations. Given these and a couple of hundred promise for capt,uring the meanings of everyday common
other facts about the words, it, sometimes (and by no means, sense. The trouble is with its basic goal: finding for each
always) manages to get the answers right. word some single rigid definition. Thats line for formalizing
But dare one say that Bobrows program really under- Mathematics. But for real life, it ignores a basic fact of
stands those sentences? If meaning isnt caught in several mind: what something means to me depends to some extent,
hundred diffcrcnt t,ricks-might not we still imprison it in on everything else I know-and no one else knows just those
several hundred thousand tricks? Is understand even an things in just those ways.
idea we can ask Science to deal with? But, you might complain, when you give up the idea
Heres how I like to deal with such questions. I feel no of ha,ving rigid, definitions, dont you get into hot wat,er?
obligation to define such words as mean and understand, Isnt ambiguity bad enough; what about the problems 01
just because others tried it for live thousand years! Our circular definitions, paradoxes, and inconsistencies? Relax!
words are only social thzngs; its great when they combine We shouldnt, be that terrified of contradictions; lets face it,
to give us good ideas. But here, I think, they only point most of the things we people think we know are crocks
to a. maze of unproductive superstitions, that only hand- already overflowing with contradictions; a little more wont,
icapped our predecessors when they tried to figure out what kill us. The best we can do is just be reasona.bly careful-and
meanings are and how they get connected to our words It tnake our machines careful, too-but still there are always
is a wrong-headed enterprise, like asking people to agree on chances of mistakes. Thats life.
Another kind of thing we scientists tend to hate are
sin fact, if there weie one less equation, it would assume that they circular dependencies If every meaning depends on the mind
mean the same, because theyre so similar its in-that is, on all other meanings in that, mind-then

8 TIE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982


theres no place to start. We fear that when some meanings Another way to know a Three is by perceptual groups.
form such a circle, then there would be no way to break into One might think of Three in terms of arranging some ob-
the circle, and everything would be too subjective to make jects into groups of One and Two. This, too, you can do
good science. mentally, without actually moving the objects, or you might
I dont think that we should fear the fact that our lay them out on a table. You might learn several different
meanings and definitions run around in vicious circles, each such arrangements:
depending on the others. Theres still a scientific way to
*
deal with this: just start making new kinds of theories-
** *
about those circles themselves! You dont have to break into ** 0

them-you only need to have good theories about them. Of * *

course, this is hard to do, and likely to get complicated It


was to avoid complication that all those old theories tried
to suppress the ways that meanings depend on one another. For Five you have more families of ways, because you can
The trouble is, that lost all the power and the richness of our use groups of Two and Three, or groups of One and Four.
wondrous meaning-webs! Lets face another fact: our minds A pentagon, a thing-filled square, a. W, a star, a plane, a.
really are complicated, perhaps more so than any other struc- cup; they all make Fives.
ture Science ever contemplated. So we cant expect the old
ideas to solve all the new problems. * * * * *
* *
Besides, speaking of breaking into the meaning-circle, * *
* * *
many science-fiction writers have pointed out that no one
* * *
ever really wants to get oneself inside another mind. No
matter if thats the only hope of perfect communication-of
being absolutely sure you understand exactly, at every level
of nuance what other people mean. The only way you could * * * *
do that is by becoming exactly like that person but even * * * * * * * *
then the game is lost,, since then you couldnt understand * * *
any more (perfectly, that is) just what it was t,hat, your old
self had tried to say.
Another strand of understanding is to know how Three
can be an incomplete or broken kind of Four--as in a defec-
What Is a Number, That a Mind Might Know It? tive square:

Now lets return to what numbers mean. This time, to * 0


make things easier, well think about Three. What could we
mean by saying that Three hasnt a.ny single, basic definition, * *
but is a web of different processes that depend upon each
other? Well, consider all t,he roles Three plays.
One way a person tells when t,heres a Three is to recite Which way is right-to count, or match, or groiip--
One, Two, Three, while pointing to the different things. which is the real meaning of a number? The very question
Of course, while doing that, you have to manage to (i) touch shows how foolish is any such idea: each structure and its
each thing once and (ii) not touch any twice. One easy way processes have both their own uses, and ways to support
to do that is, to pick up one object, as you say each counting- the others. This is what ma.kes the whole into a powerful,
word, and remove it. Soon, children learn to do that in their versatile skill-system. Neither chicken nor egg need come
minds or, when its too hard to keep track, to use some first; they both evolve from something else.
physical technique like finger-pointing. Its too bad that so many scientists and philosophers
Another way to tell a Three is to establish some Standard despise such networks and only seek to construct, simple
Set of Three things. Then you bring your set of things chains of definitions in which each new thing depends only
t,here and match them one-to-one: if all are matched and on other things that have been previously defined. That is
you have nothing left, then you had Three And, again, that what has given reductionism a bad name. The common
standard Three need not, he physical; those three words, sense meaning of Three is not a single link in one long chain
One, Two, Three would work quite well. To be sure, of definitions in the mind. Instead, we simply let the word
this might make it hard to tell which met,hod youre using- activate some rather messy web of different ways to deal
counting or matching-at the moment. Good. It really with Threes of things, to use them, to remember t,hem, to
doesnt matter, does it? (Except, perhaps, to philosophers.) compare them, and so forth. The result of this is great for
For do-ers, its really good to be able to shift and slip from solving problems since, when you get stuck with one sense
one skill-process to another without even realizing it. of meaning, there are many other things to try and do. If

THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982 9


your first idea about Three doesnt do some job, in some that shows the fundamental dialectic compromise of two
particular context, you can switch to another. But if you extremes. (So do the bears forbidden beds-too hard, too
use the mathematicians way, then, when you get into the soft, just right.) Just think of all the different kinds of Threes
slightest trouble, you get completely stuck! that confront real children in the real world, and the complex
If this is so, then why do mathematicians prefer their network of how they all relate to one another in so many
single chains to our multiply-connected knowledge-nets? different, interesting ways. There simply isnt any sense to
Why would anyone prefer each thing to depend upon as few choosing one of them to be defined so as to come beforr
other things as possible instead of as many as possible? The the rest.
answer has a touch of irony: mathematicians want to get Our culture tries to teach us that a meaning really ought
stuck! This is because, as mathematicians, we want to be to have only a single, central sense. But if you progra.mmed
sure above all that as soon as anything goes wrong, well be a machine that way, then, of course it couldnt really un-
the first to notice it. And the best way to be sure of that is to derstand. Nor would a person either, since when something
make cvcrything collapse at once! To mathematicians, t,hat has just one meaning then it doesnt really mean at all
sort of fragility is good, not bad, because it helps us find out because such mental structures are so fragile and so easy to
if any single thing that we believe is inconsist,ent with any get stuck that they havent any real use. A network, though,
of the others This insures absolute consistency-and that yields gives many different ways to work each problem And
is fine in Mathematics. It simply isnt good Psychology. then, when one way doesnt work and another does, yo11 can
Perfect consistency is not so relevant to real life because try to figure out why. In other words, the network lets you
lets face it-minds will always have beliefs that turn out think, and thinking lets you build more network. For only
to be wrong. Thats why our teachers use a very wrong when you have several meanings in a network is thcrc much
theory of how to understand things, when they shape our to think about; then you can turn things around in YOUI
chzldrens mathematics, not into robust networks of ideas, mind and look at them from different pcrspect,ives. When
but into those long, thin, fragile chains or shaky towers of you get stuck, you can try another view. But when a thing
professional mathematics. A chain breaks whenever theres has just one meaning, and you get stuck, theres no way out
just one single weak link, just as a slender tower falls when- except to ask Authority. Thats why networks arc better
ever we disturb it just a little. And this could happen to a than logical definitions There never is much meaning until
childs mind, in mathematics class, who only takes a moment you join together many partial meanings; and if you have
to watch a pretty cloud go by. only one, you havent any.
The purposes of children, and of other ordinary people,
are not the same as those of mathematicians and philosophers. Could a Computer Know About the Real World?
They need to have as few connections as can be, to simplify
their careful, accurate analyses. In real life the best ideas Is there some paradox in this idea, that every meaning
are those robust ones t,hat connect to as many other ideas is built on other meanings, with no special place to start?
as possible. And so, there is a conflict when the teachers If so, then isnt all a castle built on air? Well, yes and no
start to consult those academic technicians about curricula. Contrary to common belief, theres rea& nothzng wrong ai
If my theorys right, theyre not just, bad at that; theyre just all wzth carcular definitzons. Each part can give some mean-
about as bad at that as posszble! Perhaps this helps explain ing to the rest, Thcrcs nothing wrong with liking several
how our society arranges to make most children terrified of diflerent tunes, each one the more because it contra&s with
mathematics. We think were making things easier for them the others. Theres nothing wrong with ropes-or knots,
to find whats right, by managing to make things go all wrong or woven cloth-in which each strand helps hold the other
almost all the time! So when our children learn about num- strands toget,her-or apart! Theres nothing very wrong, in
bers (or about anything else) I would prefer that they build this strange sense, with having ones cnt,ire mind a castle in
meshy networks in their minds, not slender chains or flimsy the air!
towers. Lets leave that for when they take their graduate But then, how could such a mind have ally contact wit,h
degrees. reality. Well, maybe this is something we must always face
For learning about Two, a pre-school child learns in in any case, be we Machine or Man. 111the human condi-
terms of symmetry and congruence-two hands, two feet, tion, our mental contact with the real world is really quite
two shoes-one doesnt need to count or refer to some &an- remote. The reason WC dont notice this, and why it, isnt
dard ideal set. (It is only later that one learns that, every even much of a practical problem, is that the sensory and
time you count, you get the same result.) We learn of Three motor mechanisms of the brain (that shape the contcnt,s of,
in terms of rhymes and t,ales of Threes of Bears and Pigs and at least, our infant minds) ensure enough developmental cor-
Turtle Doves (whatever those might be) that tell of many respondence between the objects we perceive and those that.
different kinds of Threes. lie out there in raw reality; and thats enough so that we
Note that those Bears are t,wo and one, Parents and hardly ever walk t,hrough walls or fall down stairs.
Child, while their famous bowls of porridge make a very But in the final analysis, our idea of reality itself is
diffcrcnt kind of Three-too hot, too cold, just right--- rather network-y. Do triangles exist or are they only

10 THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982


Threes of Lines tha.t share their vertices? Whats real, we think were self-aware?
anyway, about a Three-in view of all weve said; reality My answer to this is that we are not, in fact, really self-
itself is also somewhat like a castle in the air. And dont aware. Our self-awareness is just illusion. I know that sounds
forget how totally some minds, for better or usually for ridiculous, so let me explain my argument very briefly. We
worse, do sometimes split away to build their own imaginary build a network of half-true theories tha.t gives us the illusion
worlds. Finally, when we build intelligent machines well that we can see into our working minds. From those apparent
have a choice: tither we can constrain them as we wish to visions, we think we learn whats really going on there. In
match each and every concept to their outside-data instru- other words, much of what we discover about ourselves, by
ments, or we can let them build their own inner networks these means, is just made up. I dont mean to say, by the
and attain a solipsistic isolation totally beyond anything we way, that those made-up ideas are necessarily better than or
humans could conceive. worse than theories we make about all other things that, we
To summarize: of course computers couldnt understand dont understand very well. But I do mean to say t,hat when
a real world-or even what a number is-were they confined we examine carefully the quality of the ideas most people
to any single way of dealing wit,h them. But neither then have about their selves-ideas they got by using that alleged
could child or philosopher. Its not a question of computers self awarcnessPwe dont find that quality very good at all.
at all, but only of our cultures foolish quest for meanings By the way, Im not saying that we arent aware of
that can stand all by themselves, outside of any mental con- sounds and sights, or even of thoughts and ideas. Im only
text. The puzzle comes from limitations of the way our saying that we arent self-aware. Im also sure that the
culture tea.ches us to think It, gives us such shallow and structures and processes that deserve to be called self and
simplistic concepts of what it means to understand that- awareness are very complicated concept-networks. The
probably-no entity could understand that way. The intui- trouble is that those are hardly at, all like what we think
tion that our public has-that if computers worked that way, theyre like. The result is that in this area our networks
they couldnt understand-is probably quite right! But this dont fit together well enough to be useful for understanding
only means we mustnt program our machines that way. our own psychology very well.
Now lets try to see what some of the meanings we attach
to self arc like. When you and I converse, it makes perfect,
sense for me to call you you and to call me me. Thats
Can a Computer Be Aware of Itself? fine for ordinary social purposes, that is, when neither of us
cares about the fine details of what is going on inside our
minds. But everything goes wrong at once as soon as ones
Even if computers do things t,hat amaze us, theyre just concerned with that-because those yous and mes conceal
mechanical They cant believe or think, feel pain or
most of the intricacy of whats inside our minds that really
pleasure, sorrow, joy. A computer cant be conscious, or
do the work The very purpose of such words like you and
self-aware-because it simply has no self to feel things
wit,h self is to symbolize away what we dont know about those
complex and enormous webs of stuff inside our head.
Well. What do you suppose happens in your head when When people talk, the physics is quite clear: I shake
someone says a thing like that to you? Do you understand it? some air, which makes your ear-drums move, and some
Ill demonstrate that this problem, too, isnt actually about computer in your head converts vibrat,ions into, say, little
phoneme units. Next, oversimplifying, these go into
computers at all. It isnt even about understanding. This
strings of symbols representing words, so now somewhere in
problem is about you. That is, it, turns around that little
your head you have something that represents a sentence.
word you. For when we feel that when we understand
The problem is, what happens next?
something, we also seem to think there must be some agent in
our hca.ds that does the understanding. When we believe
In the same way, when you see something, the waves of
light excite your retinas, and this cause signals in your brain
something, there must be someone in our heads to do the
that correspond to texture fragments, bits of edges, color
believing. To feel, someone must do the feeling.
patches, or whatever. Then these, in turn, arc put together
Now, something must, be wrong with that idea. One
(somehow) into a symbol-structure that represents a shape
cant get anywhere by assuming theres someone inside
or outline, or whatever. What happens then?
oneself-since then therell have to be another someone in-
We argued that, it, cannot help to have some inner self
side that one, to do its understanding for it, and so on. Youll
to hear or read the sentence, or little person, hiding there
either end up like those sets of nested Ukrainian Russian
to watch that mental television screen, who then proceeds
dolls, or else youll end up with some final inner self. In
to understand whats going on. And yet that seems to be
either case, as far as I can see, that leaves you just exactly
our cultures standard concept of the self. Call it t,he Single
where you started.g So whats the answer? The answer is-
we must be asking the wrong question: perhaps we never had
Actually, there might be value in imagining the Self as like those
anything like self-awareness in the first place-but only dolls-each a smaller model of the previous system, and vanishing
t,hought we had it! So now we have to ask, instead-why do completely after a few stages.

THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982 11


Agent theory: that inside every mind resides a certain spe- machines.
cial self that does the real mental work. Since this concept
is so popular, we ought to have a theory of why we all believe
such a ridiculous theory! Can a Computer Have a Self?
In fact, it isnt hard to see why we hold onto such ideas-
once we look past the single self and out into Society. For Now we can watch the problem change its character, bc-
then we realize how valuable to us is this idea of Single Agent fore our eyes, the moment that we change our view Usually,
Self-no matter how simplistic, scientifically-in social mat- we say things like this:
ters of the greatest importance. It underlies, for instance, all A computer cant do (xxx), because it has no self.
the principles of all our moral systems; without it, we could
have no canons of responszbality, no sense of blame or virtue, And such assertions often seem to make perfect sense-
no sense of right or wrong. In short, without the idea of a until we shed that Single Agent view. At once those sayings
Single Self, wed scarcely have a culture to begin with. It also turn to foolishness, like this:
serves a crucial role in how we frame our plans and goals, A computer cant do (xxx), because all a comput~cr can
and how we solve all larger problems-for, what use could do is execute incredibly intricate processes, perhaps mil-
solving problems be, without that idea of a self to savor and lions at a time, while constructing elaborately interactive
exploit their solutions. structures on the basis of almost unimagineably ramified
And, furthermore, that image of a single self is central networks of interrelated fragments of knowledge
to the very ways we knit our personalities together-albeit
It doesnt, make so much sense any more, does it? Yet.
though, as Freud has pointed out, its not the image of us
all we did was face one simple, complicated fact. The second
as we are that counts, but as wed like to be, that makes us
version shows how some of our skepticism about computers
grow. Thats why I didnt mean to say that it is bad to have
emerges from our unwillingness to imagine what might hap-
Illusions for our Selves. (Why, what could one prefer to that,
pen in the computers of the future. The first, version shows
anyway?) And so, in short, no matter that it bollixes up our
how some of our skepticism emerges from our disgracefully
thinking about thinking; I doubt if we could survive without
empty ideas about how people really work, or feel, or t,hink.
that wonderful idea of Single Self.
Why are we so reluctant to admit this inadequacy? It
To build good theories of the mind, well have to find
clearly isnt just the ordinary way we sometimes repress
a better way. We find that hard to do because the con-
problems that we find discouraging. I think it is a deeper
cept of the Single Self is so vitally important for those other
thing that makes us hold to that belief in precious self-
reasons lo But,, just as Science forced us to accept the fact
awareness, albeit, its too feeble t,o help us explain our
that what we think are single things-like rocks or mice or
thinking-intelligent or otherwise. Its closer t,o a childish
clouds-must sometimes be regarded as complicated other
excuse-like something made me do it, or I didnt really
kinds of structures, well simply have to understand that
mean to-that only denies Single Self when fault or blame
Self, too, is no elementary particle, but an extremely com-
comes close. And rightly so, for questioning the Self is ques-
plicated construct,ion.
tioning the very notion of identity-and underneath Im sure
We should be very used to this. Theres nothing wrong
were all aware of how too much analysis could shred the
with the idea of Single Houses, either. They keep us warm
fabrics of illusion that clothe our mental lives.
and dry, we buy them and sell them, they burn down or
I think thats part,ly why most people still reject com-
blow away; theyre things all right but just up to a point.
putational theories of thinking, although they have no other
But when you really want to understand how Houses work,
worthy candidates And that leads to denying minds to
then you must understand that Houses arent really things
machines. For me, this has a special irony because it was
at all but constructions. Theyre made of beams and bricks
only after trying to understand what computers-~ that is,
and nails and stuff like that, and theyre also made of forces
complicated mechanisms-could do, that, I began to have
and vectors and stresses and strains. And in the end, you
some glimpses of how a mind itself might work. Of course
can hardly understand them at all without understanding
were nowhere near a sharp and complete theory of how
the intentions and purposes that underlie the ways theyre
human minds work-yet. But, when you think about it,
designed.
how could we ever have expected, in the first place, to un-
So this wonderful but misleading Single Agent, Self idea
derstand how minds work until aft,er expertise with theories
leads people to believe machines cant understand, because
about very complicated machines? (Tlnless, of course, you
it makes us think that understanding doesnt need to be
had the strange but popular idea that minds arent compli-
constructed or computed-only handed over to the Self-
cated at all, only different from anything else, so theres no
a thing t,hat, you can plainly see, there isnt room for in
use trying to understand them.)
Ive mentioned what I think is wrong with popular ideas
Similarly, we find Einst,eins space-time integration very difficult
of self-but what ought we to substitute for t,hat? Socially,
because, no matter how it bollixes up our thinking about Special
Relativity, I doubt if we could survive without that wonderful idea of as Ive hinted, I dont recommend substituting anything-~ its
Separate Space too risky. Technically, I have some ideas but this is not the

12 THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982


place for them. The general idea is to first develop bett,er (sometimes, anyway) the things an expert needs to know can
theories of how to understand the webs of processes we (or be quite few and simple, however difficult, they ma,y be to
our machines) might use to represent our huge networks of discover or learn in the first place. Thus, Galileo was very
fragments of common-sense knowledge. Once weve some of smart indeed, yet when he saw the need for calculus, he
those that seem to work, we can begin work on other webs couldnt manage to invent it. But any student can learn it
for representing knowledge about the first kind. Finally, we today.
work on sub-webs-within those larger webs-that represent The knowledge network built into Slagles program had
szmplified theories of t,he entire mess! Theres no paradox only some 100 facts-yet thats enough to solve those col-
at all in this, provided one doesnt become too greedy-i.e., lege level problems. Most of these were simple facts about
by asking that those simplified models be more than coarse algebra and calculus, but some were about ways to tell whzch
approximations. of two problems is probably the easier. Those were especially
To do this will be quite complicated-but rightly so, for important because they embodied the progra.ms ability to
only such a splendid thing would seem quite worthy as a make judgments about situations. Without them the pro-
theory of a Self. For just as every child must connect a gram could only thrash about; wit,h them it could usually
myriad of different ways to count and measure and compare, make progress by making good decisions about what next to
in order to understand that simple concept of number, so try.
each child must surely build an even more intricate such net- Today we know a lot about making that sort of expert
work, in order that it understand itself (or even just a wishful program, but we still dont know nearly enough to build
image of itself) enough to grow a full-fledged personality. No good common sense problem solving programs. Consider
less will do. the kinds of things lit,tle children can do. Winograds pro-
gra.m needed ways to combine different kinds of knowledge:
about shapes and colors, space and time, words and syntax,
Could a Computer Have Common Sense?
and others, just to do simple things inside that childrens
world of building blocks; in all it needed on the order of
We all enjoy hearing those jokes about the stupid and
a thousand knowledge fragments, where Slagle needed only
literal behavior of computers, about how they send us checks
about a hundred-although the one just played with toys
for $0.00 or bills for $0.00 and so forth Surely that total
while the other could solve college level problems. As I see
lack of common sense has encouraged most of us to doubt
it, experts often can get by with deep but narrow bodies
machines could have minds. It, isnt just that they do only
of knowledge-while common sense is almost always techni-
what theyre told, it also that theyre so dumb that its
cally a lot more complicated.
almost impossible to tell them how to do things right.
Nor is it just a mere matter of quantity and quality of
And, indeed, those stories are quite true, on the whole.
knowledge: Winograd needed more dzfferent kznds of ways
There certainly does seem something queer about computers.
for processes to control and exploit each other. It seems that
Why, for example, can they bc so good at, advanced mathe-
common sense thinking needs a greater variety of different
matics, a.nd stuff like that, so hard for us mortals-yet seem
Icinds of knowledge, and needs different kinds of processes.
so dumb in general? You can hardly blame people for feel-
And then, once there are more different kinds of processes,
ing that there must be some vital missing element in a
there will be more different kinds of interactions between
computer!
them, so we need yet more knowledge
On the surface, this seems to apply even to those AI
To make our robots have just, their teeny bit of com-
programs. Isnt it odd, when you think about it, that the
mon sense, and that was nothing to write home about, our
very earliest AI programs excelled at advanced, adult sub-
laboratory had to develop new kinds of programming-we
jects. I mentioned that the Newell-Simon program written in
called it heterarchy, as opposed to the hierarchy of older
1956 was quite good at certain kinds of Mathematical Logic.
programs and theories. Less centralized, with Illore inter-
Then, in 196 I, James Slaglc wrote a program that could solve
action and interruption between parts of the system, one
symbolic calculus problems at the level of college students
part of Winograds program might try to parse a phrase
(it got an A on an MIT exam). Around 1965 Bobrows pro-
while another part would try to rectify the grammar wit,h
gram solved high-school algebra problems. And only around
the meaning. If one program guessed that pick is a verb,
1970 did we have robot programs, like Terry Winograds,
in Pick up the block, another progra.m-part might check
which could deal with childrens building blocks well enough
to see if block is really the kind of thing that can be picked
to stack them up, take them down, rearrange them, and put
up. Common sense requires a lot of that sort of switching
them in boxes.
from one viewpoint to another, engaging different kinds of
Why were we able to make AI programs do such grown-
ideas from one moment to another.
up things so long before we could ma.ke them do childish
In order to get more common sense into our programs, I
things? The answer was a somewhat unexpected paradox.
think well have to make them more reflective. The present
It seems that expert adult thinking is often somehow
simpler than childrens ordinary play! Apparently it can
require more to be a novice than to be an expert, because but certainly not always

THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982 13


systems seem to me a bit too active; they try too many of complex adversary processes that go on elsewhere in
things, with too little thought. When anything goes the mind, where parts of thoughts are always under trial,
wrong, most present programs just back up to previous deci- with complicated presentations of the litigants, and lengt,hy
sions and try something else-and thats too crude a base for deliberations of the juries. l3 And then, our selves hear just
making more intelligent machines. A person tries, when any- the final sentences of those unconscious judges.
thing goes wrong, to understand whats going wrong, instead How, after all, could it be otherwise? Theres no way any
of just attempting something else. We look for causal ex- part of our mind could keep track of all that happens in the
planations and excuses and-when we find them-add them rest of our mind, least of all that self)-that sketchy little
to our networks of belief and understanding -we do intel- model of the mind inside the mind. Our famous selves
ligent learning. Well have to make our programs do more are valuable only to the extent they simplify and condense
things like that. things. Each attempt to give self consciousness a much
more comprehensive quality would be self defeating; like
executives of giant corporations, they cant be burdened with
Can Computers Make Mistakes?
detail but only compact summaries transmitted from other
agents that tknow more and more about less and less. Lets
To err is human, etc. Ill bet that when we try to make
look at this more carefully.
machines more sensible, well find that knowzng what causes
mzstakes is nearly as important as knowing what is correct.
That is, in order to succeed, it helps to know the most Could a Computer Be Conscious?
likely ways to fail. Freud talked about censors in our minds,
that serve to repress or suppress certain forbidden acts or When people ask t,hat question, they seem always to
thoughts; those censors were proposed to regulate much of want the answer to be no. Therefore, Ill try to shock you
our social activity. Similarly, I suspect that we accumulate by explaining why machines might be capable, in principle,
censors for ordinary activities-not just for social taboos of even more and better consciousness than people have.
and repressions-and use them for ordinary problem solving, Of course, there is the problem that we cant agree on
for knowing what not to do. We learn new ones, whenever just what conscious means. Once I asked a student, Cam
anything goes wrong, by remembering some way to recognize people be conscious?
those circumstances, in some subconscious memory-so, Of course we can-because we are.
later, we wont make the same mistake. Then, I asked: Do you mean that, you can know every-
Because a censor can only suppress behavior, their ac- thing that happens in your mind?
tivity is invisible on the surface-except in making fewer I certainly didnt mean that I meant something
blunders. Perhaps thats why the idea of a repressive uncon- different.
scious came so late in the history of psychology. But where Well, I continued, what did you mean by conscious
Freud considered only emot,ional and social behavior, Im if you didnt, mean knowing whats happening in your mind?
proposing that theyre equally important in common-sense I didnt mean conscious of whats in my mind, just of
thinking. But this would also be just as hard to observe. my mind.
And when a person makes some good intellectual decision, Puzzled, 1 had to ask, er, what do you mean?.
we tend to ask what lint of thought lay behind it-but Well, er, its too hard to explain
never think to ask What thousand prohibitions warded off And so it goes Why can we say so littIle about our
a thousand bad alternatives? alleged consciousness? Apparently because we cant agree
This helps explain why we find it so hard to explain on what were talking about. So Ill cheat and just, go back
how our common sense thinking works. We cant detect how to self-awareness. Ive already suggested that although it
our censors work t,o prevent mistakes, absurdities, bugs, and is very useful and important, it really doesnt do what we
resemblances to other experiences. There are two reasons, think it does. We assume we have a way to discover true
in my theory, why WC cant detect them. First, I suspect facts about our minds but really, I claim, we only can make
that thousands of them work at the same time, and if you guesses a.bout, such matters. The arguments we see between
ha.d to take account of them, youd never get anything else psychologists show all too well that none of us have perfect,
done. Second, they have to do their work in a rather special, windows that look out on mental trut,h.
funny way, because they have to prevent a bad idea before If were so imperfect at self-explanation, then I dont
you get that idea. Otherwise youd think t,oo slowly to get see any reason (in principle, at Icast,) why we couldnt make
anywhere. machines much better than we are ourselves at finding out
Accordingly, much of our thinking has to be unconscious. about themselves. We could give them better ways to watch
We can only sense -that is, have enough information to the ways t,heir mechanisms work to serve their purposes and
make theories about- whats near the surface of our minds. goals. The hardest part, of course, would lie not in acquiring
Im convinced that, conscious thought is just one product such inner information, but in making the machine able

2More details of t,his t.heory are in my paper on Jokes 13Like the skeptics in Kornfelds thesis

I4 THE AI MAGAZINE Fall 1982


t,o understand it~~~that is, in building programs with the hrain-machines.
COIIIII~O~ sense theyd need in order to bc able to use such Rut when and if we chose to huild more artfully int,el-
insight, Todays programs are just too specialized, too ligent. machines, wed have more options than there were in
dumb~if youll pardon the expression- to handle anything our own evolutiorl-bccausc biology must have constrained
as complicatJed as a theory of thinking. But once we learn to the wiring of our brains, while we can wire machines in al-
make machines smart enough to understand such theories, most any way we wish. So, in the end, those artificial crca-
then (and only then) I see no special problem in giving them turcs might have richer inner lives than people do. (Do I heal
more self-insight * cries of treason?) Well, well just have t,o leave that up to
Of course, that rnight not be so wise to do-but maybe future generations-- who surely wouldnt want to build t,he
we will have t,o. For I suspect our skeptics have things upside- things that well without good reasons t,o.
down, who teach that self awareness is a strange, metaphysi-
cal appendage beyond and outside, mere intelligence, which Can We Really Build Intelligent Machines?
somehow makes us human, yet hasnt any necessary use or It will be a long time before we learn enough ahout COIIF
fnnction. Instead, it might t,urn out that, at some point, we mon sense reasoning to make machines as smart as people
have to make computers more self-conscious, just in order are We already know a lot about making useful, special-
t,o make them smart)er! It seems to me that, no robot could ized, expert systems, but WC dont yet know enough to
safely undert,alce any very complex, long-range tnsk, unless make them able to improve thcmselvcs in interesting ways.
it had st least a little insight into its own dispositions Nevertheless, all those beliefs which set mwchinc intelligence
and abilities It ought not, start a project without, know- forever far beneath our own are only careless speculations,
ing enough ahout, itself to bc pret,ty sure that it will stay based on unsupported guesses on how human minds might,
interested long cnollgh to finish. Furthermore, if it is t,o work. The best uses for such arguments are to provide op-
be able to learn new ways t,o solve hard, new kinds of prob- portunit,ies to see more ways that human minds can make
Icms, it, r113y need, again, at, least a simplified idea of how mistakes! The more WC know of why our minds do foolish
it. already solves easier, older problems. For this and other things, the better we can figure out how we so often do things
reasons, I suspect that any really robust problem solver, one so well In years to come, well learn new ways t,o make
that can adapt, to major changes in its situation, must, have machines and minds both act more sensihly Well learn
some sort of model of itself. about more kinds of knowledge and processes, and how to
On the other side, there are some minor theoretical make machines learn still more knowledge for themselves,
limitations to the quality of self-insight,. No interesting while learning for ourselves to think of thinking, feeling
machine can, in general, predict ahead of time exactly what and understanding not as single, magic faculties, but as
it will do, since it would have to comput,c faster than it complex yet comprehensible webs of ways to represent and
can comput,e So self-examination can yield only general USC ideas.
descriptions, based on simplified principles. People, too, can In turn, those new ideas will give us new ideas for new
tell us only frngments of details of how they think, and machines, and those, in turn, will further change our ideas on
usually end up saying things like It occurred to me. We ideas. And though no one can t,ell where all of this may lead,
oftan hear of mystical experiences 3nd tales of total under- one thing is certain, even now: theres something wrong wit,h
standing of the self But when we hear the things they say any claim to know, today, of differences of men 3nd possible
of what they learnetl~ it seems they only learned to quench machines- because we simply do not know enough today, of
some question-asking portion of the mind. either men or possible machines.
So consciousness yields just a sketchy, simplified mind
model, suitable only for practic.31 and social uses, but not, Automation of Reasoning: Classical Papers in
fine-grained enollgh for scientific work. Indeed, our models Computational Logic (Vol. I and Vol. II)
of ourselves seem so much weaker than t,hey ought to be that J&g II Siekman, Graham Wright.son (eds )
one suspects that syst,cmat,ic: mechanisms oppose (as Freud It is reasonable to expect that the relationship between computatson and
mathematical logac wzll be as fruitful in the next century as that between
suggested) t,hc making of too-realistic s&images. That
analysis and physics in the last .~ John McCarthy, 1963
could bc to a purpose, for what, would happen if you really Logic has emerged as one of the fundamental disciplines of comput.er
could observe your underlying goals-and were t,o say science. Computat.ional logic, which continues the tl adition of logic in
well, I dont 12,4x those goals and change them in some a new technological setting, has led to such diverse fields of application
willy-nilly way? Why, then, youd throw away an eons worth as automatic program verification, program synt.hesis, as well as logic
programming and the fifth generation comput,er system.
of weeding out, of non-survivors-since almost, every new
This series of volumes, the first coveling 1957 to 1966 and the second
invention has some fatal bug. For, as we noted earlier, a 1967 to 1970, contains those papers, which have shaped and influenced
part, of Evolutions work is rationing the creativity of OUI the field of computational logic and makes available the classical work
The main purpose of this series is to evaluate the ideas of the time and
1 think that we arc smart enough to understand t.he general principles to select papers, which can be rcgarderl as classics
of how WC think, if t.hcy wcle told t.o us Anyway, I sure hope so. But I Contents: 60 original papeTs 3 survey papers Complete bibliography
tend to (louht t.hat we have enough built-in, self-information channels on computational logic To be published by Springcl Vet lag, Berlin,
t.0 figu~ r it, out by intl ospect.ion Heidelberg, New York, 1982

TIIE AI MAGAZINE 15

You might also like