You are on page 1of 18

Lacan, Foucault, and the Crisis of the Subject: Revisionist Reflections on Phenomenology

and Post-structuralism

Louis Sass

Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, Volume 21, Number 4, December


2014, pp. 325-341 (Article)

Published by Johns Hopkins University Press

For additional information about this article


https://muse.jhu.edu/article/595136

Access provided by Smith College Libraries (15 Apr 2017 15:39 GMT)
Lacan, Foucault, and
the Crisis of the
Subject:
Revisionist Reflections
on Phenomenology and
Post-structuralism
Louis Sass

Abstract: This article offers a revisionist interpreta- French thought in the twentieth century is typi-
tion of the relationship between phenomenology and cally described as marked by a major fault line,
post-structuralism through an analysis of the post-struc- a rupture or grande coupure, that emerged in the
turalists most influential at philosophys intersection 1960s, the heyday of the crisis of the subject.
with the psy professions: Jacques Lacan and Michel
Before this time French philosophy, together with
Foucault. French structuralists and post-structuralists
sharply criticized subjectivity as a domain of study (the associated fields (including psychiatry and psycho-
primacy of consciousness) and notions of the au- analysis), were focused on issues of subjectivity
tonomous subject, arguing instead for the determining first in the vein of Bergsonian vitalism but then
role of language and other semiotic systems. I discuss shifting, with Sartre and Merleau-Ponty in the late
Heideggers role as a vanishing mediator, an influ- 1930s and 1940s, to forms of phenomenology and
ence on both phenomenology and post-structuralism existentialism inspired first by Husserl and then,
whose own focus on forms of being (the ontological
even more decisively, by Heidegger.1 But starting
dimension) undermines this assumed opposition. I
discuss the relevance for phenomenology of Foucaults mid-century, developments in the human sciences
epistemes (in Order of Things) and of Lacans registers of linguistics, anthropology, and psychoanalysis
of Imaginary, Symbolic, and Real. Finally, I consider began to offer a different perspective. Inspired by
ways in which Foucault (in Discipline and Punish) and Roman Jakobson and Claude Lvi-Strauss (both
Lacan (on ethics and the psychoanalytic act) seem to drawing on early twentieth-century linguist Ferdi-
accept elements of the traditional notion of the subject, nand de Saussure) and especially by Lvi-Strausss
including forms of freedom and responsibility, and the
attack on Sartres humanism in The Savage Mind
possibility of self-reflection.
(1962), a number of thinkers, soon to be known
Keywords: anti-humanism; ontological difference; as post-structuralists, criticized the focus on
Heidegger; episteme; structuralism; Imaginary/Sym- freedom and self-awareness, and the somewhat
bolic/Real; subjectivity; hermeneutic phenomenology;
self-congratulatory anguish, that they saw as the
Panopticon
core of phenomenology and existentialism.
2015 by The Johns Hopkins University Press
326 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

With the rise of these later thinkersthe most renounced any focus on the immanent movement
important are Jacques Lacan, Louis Althusser, Mi- of consciousness (Pluth 2007, 45). Derrida
chel Foucault, and Jacques Derridathe focus of (1967a/1973) rejected phenomenological method
theoretical attention shifted. It turned away from on the grounds that Husserls assumption of an
individual human consciousness and its dilemmas, indivisible self-presence, with its privileging of the
away from belief in the potential self-transparency actual present, the now of immanent experience,
and sovereignty (Descombes and Larmore 2009, was an egregious instantiation of the self-deceiving
182) of the subject or self2 and toward the more metaphysics of presence of Western philosophy
objective and supposedly determining structures (p. 623, 668).
of language, collective myth or ideology, and so- Anyone familiar with these ideas will have en-
cial institutions. Lvi-Strauss dismissed the focus countered what seems a stark opposition: on one
on subjectivity, individualism, the supposed side, the defenders of the self or subject and the
continuity of the self, and the allegedly self- primacy of individual subjectivity, under the aegis
evident truths of introspection; the goal was not of phenomenology, existentialism, and humanism;
to constitute but to dissolve man (1966, 250, on the other side of an abyss, the tougher-minded
256, 249). Lvi-Strauss even spoke of wishing partisans of determining semiotic structures,
to undertake the resolution of the human into marching under the banners of structuralism,
the non-human and to study men as if they post-structuralism, and the true psychoanalysis
were ants (p. 2467). Few of the later thinkers (Delacampagne 1995, 321).3 One implication of
would go quite so far. All, however, followed Lvi- this schema is that the work associated with the
Strausss lead in denouncing the primacy of con- second, supposedly anti-humanist group is as-
sciousness and the autonomy of the subject, sumed to be irrelevant, if not actually opposed, to
often associated with the so-called Cartesian the study of either subjectivity or the individual
subject (Delacampagne 1995, 321; Worms 2009, subjectexcept, perhaps, insofar as it shows these
482). The crisis in question was not restricted latter to be epiphenomena or illusions, no more
to the theoretical realm alone, but coincided with than what Foucault in 1966 called a sort of sur-
major upheavals in politics, literature (e.g., the face effect, a shimmer, a foam (quoted in Eribon
nouveau roman), and institutional life (e.g., the 1991, 161) cast up from the more decisive plane
mental asylum). of language and social structure.
It is hardly surprising that historians should There are, however, certain facts of intellec-
emphasize such an account (e.g., Descombes tual history that should make one feel uncom-
1980; Worms 2009; Delacampagne 1995; Gutting fortable with this opposition. It is interesting,
2001; Wicks 2003). They are, after all, echoing for example, that the most important so-called
statements by the key actors themselves, who post-structuralists began as adherents or close
sometimes spoke in millennial or even apocalyp- students of phenomenology: Lacan as a follower
tic terms of the death of man and in some cases of Jaspersian phenomenological psychiatry and
(e.g., Foucault [1966], following Bachelard and proponent of a vaguely existentialist paradigm
Koyr [Delacampagne 1995, 327]) were inclined (Leguil 2012, 121; Miller 2012, 10), Foucault as
to repudiate the very idea of significant histori- a champion of Binswangers Daseinanalysis, and
cal continuity in intellectual life. Lacan seemed Derrida as an appreciative if somewhat skeptical
to spurn existential psychoanalysis out of hand, student of Husserl. These can hardly be dismissed
stating that Sartre had never been willing to take as mere youthful indiscretions, given, for example,
any interest in the true psychoanalysis of Freud Lacans ambivalent but continuing relationship
(Leguil 2012, 20). Lacan dismissed as profoundly to the thought of both Sartre and Merleau-Ponty
delusional the discourse of freedom, essential (Leguil 2012), and Foucaults oft-remarked turn,
to modern man insofar as he is structured by a in his final work, to a focus on aesthetics or
certain conception of his own autonomy (Lacan techniques of the self and the ideal of deliberate
1993, 144145, 165). In an interview in 1960, he self-fashioning.
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 327

The most obvious reason to question the Existentialism is a Humanism of 1946, it is dif-
standard schema lies, however, in the fact that ficult to deny that at least some forms of so-called
one of the most influential influences on Lacan anti-humanism (a broad and oversimplifying
and Foucault as well as Derrida was none other term) stem from the heart of phenomenology itself.
than Martin Heidegger, one of the two founding All this is obviousso obvious, in fact, that one
figures of phenomenology. Indeed, it seems fairly may wonder how its implications could ever have
clear, in retrospect, that both the structuralist and been ignored. If Heideggers significance has been
post-structuralist critiques were centered, not on occluded, it is surely because he has been hiding
phenomenology in general or in its diversity, but in plain sight all along (sometimes the best way
on Sartre and Husserl in particularthe one treat- to vanish).
ed (with good reason) as an absolutist regarding In recent years, a number of writers have in fact
freedom, the other as a Cartesian foundationalist been calling attention to the influences of various
regarding method. phenomenologists on post-structuralism (regard-
Here we might think of a concept often em- ing Lacan, see Leguil [2012], Duportail [2013],
ployed by some of Lacans disciples, that of the and Phillips [1996]; regarding Foucault, see Presses
vanishing mediator (Zizek 1990). One type of Universitaires de France [2013]). Herein, I am less
vanishing mediator is an intellectual figure who interested in demonstrating influences (important
constitutes an important source of influence as they are) than in examining affinities and,
between two different intellectual positions, but in particular, in demonstrating the relevance of
whose role is conveniently forgotten in order some key poststructuralist contributions for the
to occlude some inconvenient affinities. That essentially phenomenological project of clarifying
Heidegger might be such a figure is apparent subjectivity or lived-experience and, in particular,
when one recalls his close link to both sides of for the history of the subject. I focus on two
the supposed coupure. Heidegger, after all, is the thinkers who are, in my view, the most significant
co-founder, with his early mentor Husserl, of the post-structuralists, and whose work has clearly
phenomenological tradition itself and also the key had the greatest influence at the intersections
inspiration (together with Husserl) of Sartres phi- of philosophy with psychiatry, psychology, and
losophy. Yet Heideggers workincluding writings psychoanalysis: Jacques Lacan (19011981) and
from before as well as after his famous turning Michel Foucault (19261984).
or Kehre in the 1930swas also a (perhaps the) It is useful to think of the crisis of the sub-
decisive recent influence on the most important jectespecially of his supposed freedom or self-
figures of post-structuralism, including Lacan, transparencyas involving two distinct albeit
Foucault, and Derrida. not unrelated levels. Whereas the first concerns
Consideration of Heideggers own position the qualities or capacities attributed to the actual
certainly makes it difficult to credit any sharp op- human subjectthe vision of the human person,
position between subjectivity and structure, or to or what is sometimes called philosophical anthro-
accept the polarity implicit in Foucaults reference pologythe second concerns a more epistemo-
to the question of language [laying] siege on every logical or methodological plane, pertaining to the
side to the figure of man (Foucault 1966, 417).4 philosophers or other theoreticians potential for
From early on, Heidegger questioned both the discovering the truth about the human condition
freedom and the self-transparency of the individual or human consciousness.
subject; and, especially after the 1927 publica- Sartres emphasis was largely on the first level,
tion of Being and Time, he advocated a form of as in his famous analysis in Being and Nothingness
phenomenology that increasingly emphasized the (1943) of the anguish and bad faith that afflict the
interdependence of language and human existence, individual human being. These reflect the actual
treating them as at least equiprimordial. And freedom, and the inexpungible awareness of ones
given the influence of Heideggers 1949 Letter on freedom, that, for Sartre, is an incontrovertible fact
Humanism, a sharply critical response to Sartres of our existential condition. Husserls emphasis
328 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

is more on the second level. At least in the works times, like a wholesale refusal of the very notion
published in his lifetime, Husserl says rather little of the person or individual, which are among
about the freedom or self-transparency of the the most foundational concepts of Western culture
empirical individual living her life: Does she, for (Strawson 1959). Both person and self imply,
example, experience herself as essentially free and after all, a being who is a subject of awareness,
self-aware? as a nothingness? as a founding enti- capable of experience, thought, and voluntary
ty? as a shepherd of being? Husserl does not focus action, and with a crucial capacity for self-con-
on such questions. He concerns himself far more sciousness (Honderich 1995, 655, 816).
with the potential for the philosopher to discover One might wonder, as well, about the legitimacy
the structure and operation of human subjectiv- of concepts and distinctions that have readily
ity. And here Husserl (1913; 1954) does indeed been assumed. Post-structuralism is known for
assume freedom and self-transparency. Thus, he its critique of essentialist overgeneralization and
advocates forms of reflection (the epoche and polarizing; yet this entire discussion displays all
reduction of phenomenological method) that the marks of such oversimplification, including an
require a capacity, on the part of the philosophical either/or attitude toward the existence of a self/
subject, for deliberate detachment from normal subject, and the facile assumption that certain
embeddedness (emancipation from the natural tendencies are necessarily linked. Must freedom
attitude, for example, which he describes as or self-transparency really be conceived as either
founded on a particular resolve of the will and absolute or else nonexistent? Do they always go
as an abstention through which the gaze of together like aspects of a single whole? Does a
the philosopher in truth first becomes fully free sympathy for phenomenology necessarily imply
[Husserl 1954, 145, 151]); this detachment facili- a belief in subjectivism or a sovereign self? Much
tates what Husserl describes as a quasi-Cartesian, of the original discussion has proceeded as if all
reflective self-awareness that is all-encompassing these were necessarily the case, with but rare
and possessed of potentially apodictic certitude acknowledgment of the possibility of partial or
and clarity (self-reflective clarity carried to its lim- complex types of freedom or of more shadowy
its, ultimate self-evidence [1954, 153, 189]). forms of self-awareness.
The crisis of the human subject, as understood What I would like to do here is to look beyond
by both the structuralists and post-structuralists or beneath the standard level of polemics and proc-
of mid-century Paris, is a crisis on both levels, lamations, which in my view has been taken far too
although with shifting emphasis depending on seriously. I want to ask whether this critical vision
context. The individual human beings belief (or, at associated with post-structuralism, with its sup-
least, the bourgeois Western Europeans belief) in posedly radical rejection of both subjecthood and
his subjecthood is declared an illusion. At the same subjectivity, isor need be seen as beingtruly
time, the very project of describing subjectivity is characteristic of the contributions of Foucault
called into questionboth for being impossible and Lacan, that is, of the actual concepts and
on epistemological grounds (given the supposed novel perspectives that are their most important
impossibility of valid self-reflection, and thus of legacy. In discussing both figures, I focus on key
phenomenology) and as trivial in its potential yield propositions and central periods of their careers,
(because subjectivity is but a shimmer or foam periods in which their anti-humanistic proclama-
riding atop the real events). This, at least, has tions could be at their most strident.
been the prevailing orthodoxy or ideology of both I begin with Foucaults book The Order of
structuralism and post-structuralism. It is the key Things, typically seen as heralding the triumph
lesson that figures like Lacan, Foucault, and Der- of a supposedly anti-humanist post-structuralism.
rida, and many of their followers, claim to have Then I turn to Lacan, considering especially his
drawn from Freud, Saussure, and Lvi-Strauss. key notions of the Imaginary, Symbolic, and Real.
It can be difficult to assess the real import or Finally I return again to Foucault, this time to his
seriousness of these claims. They do sound, at book Discipline and Punish. Overall, I begin with
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 329

the issue of subjectivity, considering the relevance most part does show itself. But at the same time it is
of these figures for the study of consciousness or something that essentially belongs to what initially and
the experiential dimension. In the final pages, I for the most part shows itself, indeed in such a way that
it constitutes its meaning and ground.
focus more directly on the interrelated question
But what remains concealed in an exceptional sense,
of subjecthood, namely, the ways in which each or what falls back and is covered up again, or shows
of these authors treats the questions of freedom, itself only in a distorted way, is not this or that being but
responsibility, and the possibility of self-reflection. rather, as we have shown in our foregoing observations,
It would take a book to examine these issues the being of beings. (Heidegger 1927a, 31)
in detail (see Sass 2001, 2008, 2009, in press).
Heidegger directs the phenomenologists atten-
My goal here is only to sketch some neglected
tion not to any particular object or ontic entity,
intellectual affinities and influences and, more
but to what he calls the theme of ontology, which
important, to indicate how these two thinkers,
is the overall way in which everything shows up,
typically considered post-structuralists, can be
especially regarding its felt quality of reality or
seen as contributing to the more general phenom-
the lack thereof. Ontology is possible, writes
enological enterprise, or at least to the particular
Heidegger, only as phenomenology. The phe-
line of hermeneutic phenomenology opened up
nomenological concept of phenomenon, as self-
by Heidegger. My hope is to transcend the usual
showing, means the being of beings (Heidegger
focus on schools of thought and their supposed
1927a, 31). It is this most general ontological
incompatibilities. I want, in fact, to liberate certain
dimensioncall it the worlds form or manner of
key ideas and perspectives from the constraining
presencethat is, for Heidegger, the very heart
or even suffocating environment in which they are
of our existence as subjective beings yet that is so
typically discussed. My purpose is to show the po-
readily forgotten, ignored, or distorted by reifica-
tential relevance of these notions for the phenom-
tion and other distortions that seem to come as
enological project broadly conceivedthat is, not
naturally to us as breathing. Essentially, writes
for furthering this or that particular philosophers
Heidegger, nothing else stands behind the phe-
signature approach, but for exploring subjectivity
nomena of phenomenology. Nevertheless, what is
in its disclosure of what Merleau-Ponty (1945)
to become a phenomenon can be concealed. And
called the mystery of the world (p. lxxxv). To
precisely because phenomena are initially and for
do this, however, it will be useful to recall the
the most part not given phenomenology is needed
significance of what Heidegger terms the ontologi-
(Heidegger 1927a, 31, 36 in orig.).
cal dimension, his focus on what he terms being
In a lecture course given in 1927, the year Being
(sometimes capitalized: Being) rather than beings.
and Time was published, Heidegger (1927b) de-
scribes the ontological difference (p. 72) as the
Heideggers Ontological difference between being and beings. He notes
Difference that, for a particular entity to be perceived or rec-
A crucial passage in Being and Time, for under- ognized, for example, within a given science, the
standing the entirety of Heideggers work, is one in very possibility of such an entity must first exist.
which he describes the phenomenological project (A medieval scientist could not possibly recognize
in somewhat contradictory terms: as seeking to chromosomes or photons.) Before that particular
describe something that is, at the same time, om- entity can be uncovered, the realm of its possibil-
nipresent and obvious yet also hidden and obscure. ity, its mode of being, must first be disclosed to
And this, he says, is that most decisive yet subtle the scientist. What Heidegger terms disclosure
of dimensions, the Being of entities: refers to a kind of a priori knowledge and an a
priori understanding of the beings being; it is our
What is it that phenomenology is to let be seen? mode of access to beings (p. 52, 72). Neither
.. Manifestly it is something that does not show
the scientist nor the man in the street is, however,
itself initially and for the most part, something that
is concealed, in contrast to what initially and for the
aware of this deeper, a priori dimension, the on-
tological realm of being or of disclosureeven
330 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

though it is the basis of their experience and their Foucault, The Order of Things
behavior or comportment, and even though it
determines the mode of actuality or reality, I mentioned Foucaults early sympathy for
the ontological sense of reality in general, that phenomenology as well as his late interest in an
any entity or particular being is capable of having aesthetics of the self and techniques of the self,
(p. 75, 76, 72, 74). Only rarely and momentari- which clearly imply belief in a significant degree of
ly, writes Heidegger, do scientists awaken from freedom and self-awareness. Now let us consider
their dreaming and open their eyes to the being The Order of Things (1966; originally Les mots
of the beings which they investigate (1927b, p. et les choses [Word and Things]), a book widely
54). (There are obvious affinities with the phi- understood as delivering the deathblow to human-
losophies of science of Canguilhem and Kuhn.) ism and phenomenology and as establishing the
We are speaking, then, of a foundational realm of preeminence of post-structuralism (Delacampagne
experience that is too omnipresent and immediate 1995, 334).
to be itself experienced, at least in the sense of be- This is the work in which Foucault, aiming
ing consciously recognized. Indeed, it may elude at the deepest and most implicit levels of human
even the approach of phenomenology itself, or at knowing, describes how the very experience of
least that of the early Husserl (e.g., 1913)who order itself has shifted over the course of Western
conceived phenomenology as a method whereby, history since the sixteenth centurymutating from
with the elimination of prejudices, the structures a vision of divinely ordained signatures and simi-
of experience could be clearly revealed in a form larities (in the Renaissance), to the rationalist and
of direct or immediate intuition or quasi-seeing. objectivist scientific order of the Classical Age
But how then, one may wonder, can this level of (the Enlightenment), then to the self-conscious and
disclosure be itself disclosed? potentially subjectivist categories of the modern
Heidegger describes this a priori aspect of be- or post-Kantian age in which we still live. Here
ing as a part of what he calls the perceivedness the very object of Foucaults analysis is itself epis-
of something extant which nevertheless belongs temological: the basic modes of knowing, what he
to the Dasein (1927b, 69 emphasis added)the terms epistemes, dominant in three major epochs
latter term being Heideggers attempt to refer to of Western history. Les mots et les choses focuses
the subjective sphere without implying the usual not on private existence or the individual person,
Cartesian distinctions. This quality of being or but on what governs knowledge across a variety
presence is not any kind of object and cannot be of fields during a given historical epoch, fields
treated as the object of even a direct phenomeno- that demonstrate the same general way of orga-
logical contemplation. It is what must be under- nizing knowledge despite diverse subject matters
stood if we are to carry out the project of herme- (biology, economics, linguisticsor the precursor
neutic phenomenologythat is to say, if we are disciplines of life, labor, or language).
to understand either the general human condition There can be little doubt as to Foucaults in-
or particular forms it may take on in particular tended target and imagined allies. The book ends
personalities or particular cultures, whether, for with the famous image of the figure of man (the
example, these latter be anxious or confused, essence of a supposed humanism) being erased
melancholic or schizophrenic, Greek or Judaic, like a face drawn in sand at the edge of the sea
Renaissance or modern.5 The central purpose and (1966, 422), giving way, presumably, to the tide
highest calling of phenomenology, we might say, of a new episteme that Foucault (e.g., p. 407416)
is to disclose this dimension of disclosure. It is explicitly associates with the structuralist disci-
to bring to explicit or theoretical awareness this plines of linguistics, ethnology, and psychoanalysis
ontological sense of reality in general, the deepest (Saussure/Jakobson, Lvi-Strauss, Lacan). In the
and most decisive level of our experiential lives. preface to the English translation, written a few
years later, Foucault even states that if there is
one position he does reject, it is what, broadly
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 331

speaking, could be called the phenomenological ing and ground (Heidegger 1927a, 31) of what
approach. Such an approach, he says, gives abso- is manifest in our experience, the a priori knowl-
lute priority to the observing subject [the notion of edge and an a priori understanding of the beings
self-transparency], attributes a constituent role being (Heidegger 1927b, 52) Foucault speaks
to an act [the issue of freedom], places its own similarly of seeking conditions of possibility and
point of view at the origin of all historicity, a positive unconscious of knowledge, and of
in short, leads to a transcendental consciousness an historical a priori level that can seem con-
[subjectivism]. To such a theory of the knowing fused and obscure yet is most fundamental of
subject Foucault declares his preference for a all (Foucault 1966, 72). Foucault even uses the
theory of discursive practice (p. xv). b-word repeatedly. He speaks, for example, of
Yet it would be mistaken to read this as a rejec- the pure experience of order and of its modes of
tion of phenomenology in all its forms. Les mots being, the mode of being of the objects that ap-
et les choses is obviously highly sympathetic to pear in [a] field, and discourse and mans being
structuralism. But Foucault (in the same preface) (1966, 366); and states that the present study is
disputes certain half-witted commentators an attempt to analyze that experience (emphasis
in France who have persisted in labeling him a added). We might say that Foucaults object is the
structuralist, lamenting that he has been unable same as what Heidegger describes, in his lecture
to get it into their tiny minds that [he has] used course, as the perceivedness of the perceived. It
none of the methods, concepts or key terms that is something that belong[s] in a certain sense to
characterize structural analysis. (Foucault goes the object, to the perceived, yet is rooted in the
on to pay homage to structuralism, referring to a Dasein or knowing subject, which in Foucaults
connection that does me honor, but that I have case is understood as a kind of collective or cul-
not deserved [p. xv].) tural/historical subject, an episteme.
Foucaults demurral is accurate enough. Unlike Foucault is interested, in fact, not just in dem-
Lvi-Strauss, for example, his own general meth- onstrating the general presence of structure, or
od, at least in this book, in identifying epistemes even of certain particular structures as such, but
does not seek basic elements that are organized in examining the ontological implications of the
in terms of structural oppositions, nor does he epistemes he delineates, which is to say, the most
assert that this is how actual humans necessarily general or foundational way in which they convey
function.6 The Renaissance episteme, as he con- an experience of reality or of Being.
ceives it, for example, operates not according to There is indeed a difference in the overall sense
the diacritical principles of structural opposition of actuality or reality, and of ones relationship to
between polarized identities, but in accord with it, when one feels oneself to be living in the pres-
various modes of experienced similarity or resem- ence of the following three forms of being: the
blance, modes in which experienced meaning is divinely ordained (and magic-friendly) pattern
far from being mere shimmer or foam (quoted of similarities and signatures of the Renaissance;
in Eribon 1991, 161). Foucaults analysis of the the purely objective order of the Enlightenment or
modern era is still further from structuralism, Classical Age, which rejects the very category of
given that here the fundamental category is actu- similarity as superficial, emphasizes measurement
ally self-consciousness, the post-Kantian tendency or analysis into units, and views names as but
of the subject to take itself as the supposed basis arbitrary labels rather than divine signatures; and
for all knowing while also taking itself as the finally, what Foucault termed the transcendental
prime object of knowledge (thus falling into the narcissism (1969, 203) of the modern, post-
paradoxical condition that Foucault termed the Kantian era that we are still caught inside, the
empirico-transcendental doublet). era in which language becomes object and the
Foucaults way of describing his project is, empirical sciences become linked with reflections
in fact, highly reminiscent of Heideggerwho on subjectivity (1966, 239, 321, 270). Foucault
speaks, as noted, of disclosing the hidden mean- speaks, for example, of experiencing the raw
332 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

being of language in the Renaissance and of Foucault, Cervantes work demonstrates a grow-
how that experience has been forgotten since ing discomfort with the modes of order and forms
the sixteenth century (p. 48), after which words of credulity (based on resemblance, as in the case
(during the Enlightenment) came to be understood of Don Quixote mistaking windmills for knights
as arbitrary labels harboring no necessary clue to or scullery maids for princesses) characteristic of
the essence of what they designate. the Renaissance episteme. It is as if Cervantes were
What Foucault describes as the difference somehow anticipating the immanent transition
between Renaissance and Enlightenment has, in into, and retrospective view from, the more sober
fact, something in common with the shift between perspective of the Enlightenment. In the latter
a religious/Aristotelian and a Galilean universe as episteme or mode of being, things cannot be taken
described by historian of science Alexandre Koyr to be what they may seem to be on the basis of
(a significant influence on Foucault) in From the (mere) resemblance. The play of similitudes is now
Closed World to the Infinite Universe. But closer suspect. It is no longer an enigmatic but poten-
analogies to Foucaults epistemes are the distinct tially revelatory domain of deepest truth (Foucault
forms of being invoked by the later Heidegger 1966, 30), but only a fabric of illusion, born of
(1977) when he contrasts the worlds of the Greek human fantasy, that obscures the deeper ground
temple, Gothic church, and hydroelectric dam of material reality, the realm that any sober person
although Foucault focuses more on something like might measure, touch, or see. Foucault (1966)
underlying codes and categories. This, of course, describes Don Quixote as the hero of the same:
is a form of phenomenology, albeit one that dif- his whole journey [is] a quest for similitudes,
fers profoundly from that of at least the early but in a new world in which similitudes have
Husserl. It is hermeneutic/interpretive rather than become deceptive and verge upon the visionary or
Cartesian/foundationalist in its methodology. (It madness. In Cervantes novel, the cruel reason
may also exemplify what Husserls follower Eugen of identities and differences makes endless sport
Fink (1985/1995, 5565) described as construc- of signs and similitudes [and] language breaks off
tive phenomenology.) In its vision of its human its old kinship with things (pp. 514).
object (the epistemes), it insists on the collective, The intensely phenomenological character of
horizonal, and non-self-transparent nature of what Foucaults interest is even more obvious in his
it describes, and on the crucial importance of the elaborate analysis of the experience of looking
overall ontological dimension of the experience at Velasquezs painting, Las Meninas. Foucaults
of Being. appreciation of a paintings potential to reveal an
Les mots et les choses is a book that many entire lived-world, together with his analysis of
have found exceedingly obscure. Much of its dif- the interplay of gazes depicted on the canvas, are
ficulty, as well as its lyricism, probably stems from highly reminiscent of both Merleau-Ponty and
Foucaults awareness of the challenge of evoking Sartre. Foucaults (1966) main emphasis, however,
dimensions of knowledge that (as Heidegger un- is on the ontological issues typical of Heideggers
derstands) clearly verge on the ineffable. These are hermeneutic phenomenology, which is to say, on
not structures that can simply be seen, in any sense the way Velasquez painting can be understood to
of the latter term. They are not revealed before a reveal the overall mode of being of the Enlight-
purified gaze, but must be elicited or imagined, fur- enment or Classical Ageto serve, as it were, as
ther clarified, and only then, perhaps, recognized. the representation of Classical representation
Foucaults essentially phenomenological inter- (p. 17). Thus, Foucault calls our attention to the
est in what he himself calls the experience of importance of the sense of a looming void, in the
order and its modes of being (emphasis added) midst of a wholly realistic world, that is evoked
emerges with particular force in his discussions by the absence from the canvas of the royal pair,
of Don Quixote (1605/1615) and Las Meninas the king and queen. (We only see them reflected,
(1656), two works poised at the transition (circa ghostlike, in a distant mirror: figures of absence,
1650) from Renaissance to Classical Age. For two tiny silhouettes gleaming out from the
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 333

looking-glassthe palest, the most unrealof all Lacans Three Registers


the paintings images [p. 5, 15].) This absence is
both peculiar and distinctive: the king and queen The phenomenological implications of Lacans
are not only the object of all the gazes depicted (1953a) contribution can best be demonstrated
in the canvas (everyone is looking toward them, by considering the core of his theoretical vision,
which is also toward us, the viewers, who stand in which is his notion of the three registers of human
the spot where the painter, Velasquez, must have reality: Real, Symbolic, and Imaginary (sometimes
been); they also constitute the standpoint from abbreviated as RSI). At first this may seem surpris-
which everything is seenwhat Foucault describes ing, given that each concept clearly does imply, on
as the gaze which has organized it and the gaze some level, a confrontation with what might be
for which it is displayed (p. 17). For Foucault, termed the illusory nature of our lived experience.
this is emblematic of the Classical experience of Closer consideration shows that each of these no-
being. It demonstrates how, in this episteme, nearly tions can, in fact, also be understood in a rather
everything can be given a realistic, in a sense ob- different light.
jective, representationeverything, that is, with Let us start with Lacans overtly anti-phenom-
the crucial exception of the constituting viewer, a enological thrust, beginning with the Imaginary
being who will be thematized only later, by Kant register as presented in his famous analysis of the
and all that follows in his wake.7 mirror stage. Here Lacan (1966, orig. 1949) sug-
We see, then, that Foucaults project in Les gests that our sense of having an autonomous ego
mots et les choses is an eminently Heideggerian or self is, in fact, a sort of subjective illusion (the
one: that of disclosing forms of disclosure, of illusion of being a subject, or at least a certain kind
revealing the characteristic structures of distinct, of subject: coherent and in control), and that this
culturally grounded forms of subjectivity. Anyone illusion is based on internalizing the objective im-
who might attempt to grasp the lived-world of a age we see of ourselves in a mirror or other source
Renaissance, Enlightenment, or modern individual of reflection. Lacan himself offers his argument as
would do well to bear in mind the overall ways of a refutation of a notion, epitomized by Sartre and
experiencing meaning and reality, together with presumably accepted by phenomenology (he refers
characteristic forms of credulity and doubt, that dismissively to the contemporary philosophy of
Foucault describes in his analysis of these epis- being and nothingness). This is the notion that one
temes.8 The disclosure of these fundamental forms is indeed an autonomous and self-aware subject (a
of disclosure clearly requires hermeneutic methods self-sufficiency of consciousness [and] the illusion
that go beyond the purifying subtractions inherent of autonomy [p. 99100]), and that this truth is
in the phenomenological and other Husserlian somehow incontrovertible, an immanent fact of
reductions, a method Heidegger considered insuf- experience itself.
ficiently sensitive to the ontological difference. It is The anti-phenomenological import of the Sym-
nonetheless a phenomenological project, focused bolic Order (1953a, 1953b) seems equally telling.
on experience or the lived-world, indeed on the Here, Lacan presents a realm that is understood to
subtlest and most fundamental yet least objectifi- lie beyond our conscious grasp (a realm of semiotic
able dimensions of subjective life. One should structures encompassing the unconscious, which is
note as well that it is impossible to dismiss these structured like a language), yet which, in contrast
modes of disclosure that are disclosed in Foucaults with the illusions of the imaginary realm, sup-
book as mere epiphenomena or surface effects posedly constitutes the actual matrix and motor
(shimmer or foam), for it is obvious that these of much of our experience and action. For Lacan,
underlying modes organize the culture, and with as for Lvi-Strauss before him, it is clear that we
this the behavior and expression (what Heidegger are not the masters of the language-like structures.
calls the comportment) of human beings.9 Regardless of what our immediate experience may
seem to tell us, it is language that speaks us rather
than the reverse.
334 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

The anti-phenomenological thrust may seem tributes to phenomenology, not that he is entirely
most obvious of all in Lacans discussion of his or solely a phenomenologist.) Here I have space
third register of the Real (1953a, 1993, 2007). only to sketch these dimensions.
Here, after all, we are dealing with a realm that That the Imaginary, despite its generating of il-
is, in some sense, actually defined by its inacces- lusion, is a mode of experience is perfectly obvious,
sibility to our experiencea realm that Lacan as- and indeed explicit in Lacans account. In this sense
sociated with Kants notion of noumenal reality Lacans account of the imaginary realm just is, on
(reality in-itself) and that is specifically conceived one level, an account of one crucial dimension of
in contrast with the manifest, phenomenal realm what it is like to be a living human being. The
of our lived-experience. The very existence of the fact that the Imaginary is a partial, in some sense
Real may well seem the ultimate refutation of deceptive, realm, does not gainsay it own experi-
phenomenological complacency or indeed, of any ential reality, its actuality as a form of experience,
expectation that examination of our conscious- nor its relevance for a phenomenological account
ness could provide an inventory of what there is of a key aspect or dimension of subjectivity.10
or could be. The Symbolic is often described in structural
It is understandable, then, that Lacans registers terms, and in this sense is not directly a phenom-
are so often conceived as undermining any image enological fact. It should be clear, however, that
of a free and self-transparent subject or self, and Lacans Symbolic has various sorts of relevance for
also the notion that subjectivity is either an acces- our subjective lives. It does, for example, lend a
sible or a consequential realm. What these registers certain polarizing tendency to our sense of things,
seem to reveal is, rather, that our experiential lives grounded in the diacritical nature of language,
are largely illusory (the Imaginary), epiphenom- and this becomes a feature of our lived world.
enal (the Symbolic), or simply blind (the Real). But perhaps the crucial feature of the Symbolic,
Much of what I have just said about Lacans in Lacans account, is how the advent of linguistic
vision of the deceptions and blindspots of our symbolism supposedly cuts us off from a pre- or
experiential lives is not only true but crucial for sub-linguistic experience of the world that we
any understanding of his perspective. A more ex- experience, in its absence (and as an absence), as
tended consideration of each register nevertheless more authentic, and immediate, thereby tinging
shows, however, that Lacan can more accurately our very experience of being with a pervasive
be viewed as a potential contributor to, than as an aura of loss. Lacan (1960) describes this event as
enemy of, phenomenology. To see this, we need to a kind of castration, but goes on to view it as
think of phenomenology not as presupposing or the essential generator of our desire (which is, at
vindicating the sovereign or self-transparent self, bottom, the desire for a return to something that
but as a tentative and exploratory disclosure of is felt to be both primordial and forbidden, hence
subjective life in its more formal or ontological dangerous and infinitely alluringwhat Lacan re-
dimensions; not as a Cartesian project seeking fers to as the thing and the objet petit a). In these
a realm of absolute clarity and certitude (whose ways the Symbolic is of great phenomenological
possibility is assumed), but as an exploration of relevance since it both generates and constitutes
subjective life as it actually exists, with all its lim- certain modes of subjective life. One should note,
its and constraints and realms of blindness. On as well, the profound influence that Heideggers
Heideggers ontological and hermeneutic account, (1950) notion of die Sprache, understood as the
human subjectivity is not and cannot be either self- fundamental source of disclosure, had on Lacans
grounding or fully self-transparent. Bearing this (1953a, 1953b) notion of the importance of la
in mind, each of Lacans three registers or orders parole (human speech).11
can be understood as constituting something like As for the Real, it needs to be recognized that
a Heideggerian mode of Being. (This is not to say, what Lacan is interested in is not, in fact, the
of course, that this is the only way they need to actual noumenon as it really is or might be. The
be or can be understood; I argue that Lacan con- notion of the Real is, ratherat least in large
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 335

parta way of capturing the role that our sense bolic; awareness of mortality and a beyond in the
of otherness, limits, and the unknown can actually case of the Real. This is true as well of Foucaults
play in our subjective lives. The Real, we might epistemes. Humanism is a polysemic term; and it
say, is a kind of unknowable and unattainable is clear that both Foucault and Lacan show disdain
beyond that refuses to leave us alone. It is the for self-satisfied liberal humanism and engage in
unexpected surprise that confounds expectations, anti-humanist polemics. Neither, however, shows
yet assaults us again and again with implacable any real inclination toward Lvi-Strausss (1962)
repetition. One might say, then (putting things in ambition to undertake the resolution of the hu-
a maximally paradoxical way), that the Lacanian man into the non-human (p. 2467).
Real is concerned with the phenomenon of the It should be obvious, I think, that experiential
noumenonnot with the in-itself in itself, but dimensions such as those captured by Lacans
with the in-itself in-itself for us.12 registers do not and cannot lend themselves to the
One could say, then, that each of the Lacanian kind of clarity and certitude to which Husserl, in
registers describes a form of Being in the Heideg- his Cartesian moments, was drawn. It cannot be
gerian ontological sense: an overall way in which an enterprise of pure intuition or direct descrip-
one can (and does) experience the world and one- tion, relying entirely on what a given subject could
self. The imaginary is that mode of subjective life report either naively or with benefit of the various
in which what is most actual or real tends to be phenomenological reductions. Nor does it aspire
identified with that which has distinct, Gestalt-like to anything like apodictic certitude. A phenom-
form. The Symbolic is that mode in which Being enology of this kind is more in line with Heidegger,
is experienced as involving categorical polarities especially the later Heidegger, for it puts a higher
and a sense of abstraction from something more premium on the evocation of profound existential
grounded or authentic. The Real is that mode in and ontological realities than it does on hopes of
which the very eluding of our conceptual/percep- incremental progress of a methodological sort.
tual grasp serves as the ultimate index of Being. The ultimate object of phenomenology is con-
The affinities with the projects of both Heidegger sciousness or presence itself, but this is something
and Foucault should be clear. One could describe that, although omnipresent, is also hidden or
Lacan as offering an ontological characterization obscure (because it is too close to us, indeed is
of much of what Freud interpreted in more ontic us). Hermeneutic phenomenology recognizes the
(entity-like) fashion. I would note, however, that need to bring other knowledge to bear, including
Lacans vision has the advantagefor a psycholo- theories and metaphors of various kinds, so long
gistof ascribing more than a single experience of as these other forms of knowledge are in service
order or of a mode of being to a given subjectivity, of revealing the nature of consciousness. This is
in contrast with the historical analyses of both clearly a hermeneutic, dialectical, in some respects
Heidegger and Foucault. We must remember, after free-wheeling enterprise, one in which speculation
all, that Lacans three registers (RSI) are not only and imaginative hypothesizing must play a central
conflicting, but also interdependent and mutually role. It is crucial, of course, that these potential
defining. His tripartite account opens up the pos- revelations not simply be accepted without criti-
sibility of an ontological account that is more com- cism, but rather judged (itself an interpretive act,
plex and dynamic, grounded in the various forms obviously) in terms of how well they seem to
of interdependency and opposition that can exist correspond to or to capture the reality of our
between these orders or regimes (Sass, in press). subjective lives.
It should be noted, by the way, that each of
Lacans three registers is grounded in something The Subject
distinctly human, that is, in one or another feature
traditionally seen as unique to, and definitive of, Let us turn from the question of subjectivity
the human essence: self-consciousness in the case to the related but more specific issue of subject-
of the Imaginary; language in the case of the Sym- hood. The reader may now accept the relevance
336 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

of these post-structuralists for the general project of the ego/self/moi, in favor of a certain notion of
of phenomenology. But can it really be said that, the subject or sujet as a manque--tre irrduct-
despite their anti-humanist polemics, Foucault and ible (an irreducible lack-of-being; Leguil 2012, 17,
Lacan also accept, at least to some extent, the no- 103), Lacan (both early and late) borrowed from
tion of a self-conscious and self-controlling subject Sartres work on prereflective awareness. Sartres
(which, roughly speaking, would be equivalent work offers his famous desubstantialization of
to accepting some of the traditional notion of the consciousness, but it is one in which consciousness
person)?13 I touch briefly on Lacan before turning is understood both as an experience of nothingness
to Foucault. and as a condition of limitless freedom (a nant
able to nantise).
Lacan, Ethics, and the Acte Something akin to this emphasis on freedom
Lacan is often described as a sort of radical emerges in a highly enigmatic but forceful way in
anti-humanist who crusaded not only against what Lacans insistence on the possibility or even ethical
he saw as the reifications of American ego psy- necessity of what he calls the acte or psycho-
chology, but also against any notion of a free or analytic acta moment in which the subject,
self-aware subject. It is true that Lacan dismissed says Lacan, is most fully activated (Gallagher
voluntarism: the term freedom, he said, makes 2002, 11). Lacan does not, so far as I can judge,
me laugh; I never talk about freedom (Pluth offer any clear philosophical formulation of his
2007, 4). But, as more discerning scholars have positionthat is, of just how to integrate these
argued (e.g., Leguil 2012, 85; Zizek 2000), Lacan claims with his insistence on the decisive role of the
does not in fact attack the subject tout court so notion of the unconscious; perhaps he recognizes
much as seek a new notion of the subject, one that clear formulation of this problematic synthesis
more linked to language and the unconscious, is impossible. The echoes of Kierkegaards notions
and therefore more reflective of its problematic of freedom and the leap of faith, and of the acte
or paradoxical status. gratuite of Gide, Sartre, and Camus, seem clear
It would be impossible here to enter into the enough, however. The acte psychoanalytique
complexities of Lacans notion or notions of the (to be distinguished, incidentally, from passage
subject. It seems obvious, however, that Lacans lacte and acting-out) seems to be some kind of
rejection of free will is far from absolute. This extreme albeit paradoxical expression of freedom,
should be clear from the mere fact that he speaks of involving a simultaneous recognition and refusal
an ethics of psychoanalysis (Miller 1992), given of all imaginable constraints. One Lacanian dis-
that ethical responsibility is inconceivable in the ciple speaks of it as implying an ability to break
absence of at least some degree of freedom, com- through the limit imposed by the phantasy and
promised and complicated though it may be. Sartre thus to call into question our attachment to the
and Lacan have often been considered antithetical symptom (Melman in Gallagher 2010, 21).
figures on the issue of freedom. But as Leguil has Another influential Lacanian goes so far as to
shown in her recent Sartre with Lacan (2012, 85), interpret it as both totally free and profoundly
there are actually many affinities, including that consequential: In an authentic [Lacanian] act
of Lacans divided subject with Sartres pour-soi. I do not simply express, or actualize my inner
Both she and Jacques-Alain Miller (Lacans son-in- nature. I rather redefine myself, the very core of
law and orthodox intellectual heir) have recently my identity (Zizek 1999, also 1997). At least on
argued, in fact, that Lacan, in speaking of the this account, the Lacanian acte is something that
psychotic patients insondable decision de ltre is wholly unpredictable and undetermined; stem-
(unfathomable decision of being) seems to have ming from nowhere, yet somehow simultaneously
adopted something very close to Sartres notion of aware of its own freedom from necessity and of
a fundamental existential choice (le choix origi- its own overwhelming significance.
nal) as central to human life (Leguil 2012, 26, 33;
Miller 2012, 9). It also seems that, in his critique
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 337

Foucaults Discipline and Punish register, as well, an implicit questioning of the kind
In concluding, I turn again to Foucault, this of self-transparency epitomized by the Husserlian
time to Discipline and Punish (1975). Whereas epoche, at least insofar as the latter assumes an act
The Order of Things is inspired, in large measure of autonomous and volitional self-founding. In
by an animus (misconceived, as I have argued) all these ways, it would seem, Foucault separates
against phenomenology, against the very idea of himself from the ethos of phenomenology and
taking subjectivity as ones object, Discipline and existentialism, with their characteristic focus on
Punish is more directed against the notion of the subjectivity and the subject.
subject. An implicit project of this book about dis- A bit of thought, however, should make one
cipline and surveillance is to undermine our faith question the cleanness of this separation. First
in the modern sense of autonomy, self-awareness, we should note that the key notion of panopti-
and self-control. Here the target, we might say, cism seems inseparable from phenomenological
is less transcendental narcissism than a kind of concerns, insofar as it is concerned with not only
transcendental egotism: not the mere attending to the genealogy but also the form of a certain kind
our own consciousness, but the prideful claiming of modern subjectivity. The very structure of the
of autonomy and self-control. Panopticon implies the presence of a specific kind
Foucault describes Discipline and Punish, per- of subjectivity, the very sort, obviously, that it itself
haps his most famous book, as intended to offer is intended to bring about. And this, of course, is
a correlative history of the modern soul and of a the divided self of modern, self-monitoring sub-
new power to judge, a genealogy of the modern jectivity. It is a form of experiential life emptied
soul grounded in a history of punitive power of spontaneity and dominated instead by a sense
(1975, 23, 29). This is the work in which Foucault of taking oneself as ones own object and thus of
describes the famous image of the Panopticon, being divided between an observing and observed
offering this as an emblem of the general disciplin- part. R. D. Laings The Divided Self describes
ary order in which the modern, self-monitoring analogous forms of subjective life, as does the
self and sense of interiority has supposedly been account by sociologist Norbert Elias of various
forged. The import of Foucaults analysis is to aspects of modern interiority.
portray the modern humanistic senses of self- Foucaults image of the Panopticona ma-
awareness and self-control in a most unhealthy chine for dissociating the see/being seen dyadis
light. They are presented not as the self-founding, just the sort of historically rooted image and
intrinsically liberating expressions of individual theory that can enrich a hermeneutically oriented
initiative that they may seem, but, rather, as the phenomenological analysis. I myself have used it
products of subjectification, of an oppressive but to offer a detailed phenomenological interpreta-
anonymous regime that reproduces itself blindly tion of the lived-world and self-experience of one
via processes that serve, not the individual, but famous and perhaps paradigmatic patient, Daniel
the requirements of an isolating yet homogenizing Paul Schreber, whose subjective existence is best
social order. understood (so I argue) as a particularly extreme
Foucault can certainly be enigmatic; his attack instance of a kind of lived panopticism (Sass 1987,
on humanism, at least in its autonomy-obsessed 1992 chap 8). The patients delusional beliefs
form, seems obvious enough however. He goes (which are largely centered on the interaction of
so far as to state that it is on the basis of the what he calls rays and nerves, corresponding
panoptical, disciplinary order that various con- to the watching and watched parts of the divided
structs have been constructed, including those of stream) can, for example, be read as a sort of in-
psyche, subjectivity, personality, consciousness ner allegory of this specific form of subjectivity.
(1975, 29). Whereas Sartre famously insisted But what if we consider neither subjectivity nor
that even the prisoner is free, Foucault claims the subjective illusion of self-hood, but the subject
that panoptical imprisonment generates what is or self itself, that is, taken as a reality? Discipline
only the illusion of freedom. Perhaps we should and Punish might at first seem to present itself
338 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

(albeit obliquely) as an attack on the very idea shows himself capable of transcending the suppos-
that autonomy and self-awareness could be more edly blinding condition in which he himself must
than subjective illusions, perverse products of residewhich in this case is not the Panopticon,
the disciplinary order. To think clearly here, it is but the supposedly self-refuting and self-deceiving
necessary to remove ourselves from the polarized condition of the empirico-transcendental doublet
ideological currents that dominated the era of the and transcendental narcissism (the condition
crisis of the subject. For even if we accept the role in which, as Foucault himself says, we are still
of the Panopticon in molding the self, there is no caught). Foucault, at least, seems to have man-
reason to deny the reality of this self, a self that, aged to wake up from his anthropological sleep
on Foucaults own explicit account, is nothing if (1966, 371) enough to be able to discern the very
not consequential. The modern subject, molded forms of blindness within which the modern, self-
by processes of panoptical subjectification, does, conscious self might have seemed to be entirely
after all, both accurately scrutinize and effectively enclosed.14 But this inevitably suggests that self-
control its own behavior, at least to a significant consciousnessand at least some of the freedom
extent. If having causal powers is a criterion of and insight it impliesmust be something more
the real, then surely the panoptical subject is very than mere illusion. Yes, we may delude ourselves
far from being a mere illusion. This truth is inde- about the extent or motivation of our autonomy
pendent of the fact that, on Foucaults account, and self-control; yes, we may exaggerate the reli-
the modern soul may also be quite ignorant of ability and scope of our self-reflection. But as we
its actual genealogy (in the Panopticon, etc.) and have seen, this is very far from refuting the very
thus deluded about its own deeper motivations. existence of a self or subject, or from dismissing
Beyond this, on a more abstract philosophical subjectivity, the focus of the phenomenological
level, we might ask whether the creation of such a tradition, as a theme of cardinal importance.
self-monitoring subject would even be imaginable All these points, taken together, show the ab-
in the absence of some sort of minimal- or proto- surdity of reading either Discipline and Punish or
self, some inherent capacity for self-consciousness The Order of Things as a simple attack either on
and self-control that is elicited and exploited by the the self or on the possibility of some form of valid
new disciplinary regime. Surely it is more plausible reflection. Much the same can be said of the work
to imagine the Panopticon as eliciting and shaping of Jacques Lacan. As we have seen, both authors
an inherent feature of human consciousness than are preoccupied with distinctively human dimen-
as creating it out of whole cloth. In this sense, sions of culture and the person. Both need to be
Discipline and Punish cannot be viewed as a total understood as making important contributions to
rejection of the reality of subjecthood, even though the philosophy as well as the history of the subject,
it obviously undermines any image of complete with the latter conceived, in large measure, as a
sovereignty or absolute self-transparency. Fou- quintessentially phenomenological project.
caults imminent turn, in his work on sexuality
and the ancient world, to techniques of the self Notes
and self-fashioning may now begin to seem a bit 1. Bergsonian vitalism is evident in work of phenom-
less drastic and unprecedented. enological psychiatrist Eugene Minkowski. Delacam-
A final point concerns the epistemological pagne (1995, 210) dates the triumph of Heidegger in
plane: the position of Foucault himself, the France to a 1955 meeting at Cerisy-la-Salle organized
by Jean Beaufret and attended by Lacan; Heideggers
theoretician. Does not Foucaults very ability to
influence began much earlier however.
describe the modern disciplinary regime imply a 2. The French, especially in philosophicalcontext,
certain insight and freedom from its constraints, distinguish between le sujet, or le je, and le moi (the
at least on the part of one subject (and his many subject, or the I, versus the me), the former referring to
readers)? Much the same could be said with re- the subjective pole of experience and action (the expe-
gard to Les mots et les choses. There too Foucault riencer or actor), while the latter refers to something
the theoretician, in the very writing of his book, more like an image of oneself, taken as an object. The
English term self is used in both senses.
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 339

3. Like most such terms, post-structuralism is a (of their own constituting perspective) that should be
loose label with fuzzy boundaries. It covers a diverse impossible on a strictly anti-humanistic reading of the
set of works and positions influenced by structuralism supposedly all-determining nature of an episteme.
(including its critique of phenomenology and the Carte- 10. The very rhetoric of the mirrorstage essay, in
sian ego and its focus on underlying systems), but that fact, clearly presupposes, on the part of the reader,
also criticize structuralism (e.g., Derrida 1967b/1978) at least some capacity to evoke in oneself, to reflect
and/or move beyond its usual concerns into other issues, upon, and to assess experiences like those of standing
including politics, psychology, and problems of identity. before a mirror or in the gaze of another. In this sense
4. I am aware, of course, that Heidegger would reject a significant degree of, if not self-transparency, at least
the word subjectivity as irredeemably Cartesian. In an self-translucency does seem to be assumed on the part
essay of this kind, concerned with comparative issues, of the reader. Indeed it is difficult to see how a medita-
it would be fruitless to attempt to adhere strictly to tion like that of Lacan on the Imaginary could get off
Heideggers own preferred vocabulary. the ground without some such assumption. In this sense
5. Re different experiences of being in psychotic de- the mirror-stage essay and analysis simply assumes the
pression and schizophrenia, see Sass and Pienkos 2013. possibility of phenomenology. In the context of another
6. Foucaults own approach is of course akin to of his analyses, Lacan asks, Is this a correct phenom-
structuralism in the broad sense of focusing on dis- enological analysis? (1964, 84).
course and seeking underlying principles or forms of 11. Lacan (1956) translated into French Heideggers
knowledge. important Logos essay on Heraclitus, in which Being
7. Foucault describes the profound invisibility of is identified with language itself.
what one sees [as] inseparable from the invisibility 12. Lacans formulations of the Real do not empha-
of the person seeingdespite all mirrors, reflections, size the experiential dimension alone. He writes that
imitations, and portraits (1966, 17). He speaks of the real is radically distinguished from the symbolic
an essential void: the necessary disappearance of that and the imaginarythe real is the impossible also in
which is its foundationThis very subjecthas been a logical sense; there are logical obstacle[s] to its
elided (p. 18). Within that reality itself, it [the subject] formulation or conception (Lacan 196970, 123).
cannot not be invisible. (p. 16). 13. Derrida (Nancy 2009) seems to have recognized
8. To understand the complexities of modern or this point re Lacan, as in this statement: Did Lacan
contemporary (post-Kantian) forms of subjectivity and liquidate the subject? No. The decentered subject of
self-consciousness, one should consider Foucaults dif- which he speaks certainly doesnt have the traits of the
ficult but illuminating analysis of the self-inflationary classical subject (though even here, wed have to take
yet self-undermining paradoxes of our modern forms of a closer look).
transcendental narcissismwhat Foucault describes 14. Various writers have pointed out that this tran-
as a sleep so deep it experiences itself as vigilance scending or awakening raises the issue of performative
(1969, 203; 1966, 341). I have tried to do this in several self-contradiction. For a critical perspective see Seigel
works: Sass 1992 chap 11, 1997, 2008, 2009. 2005; for defense of Foucault on this issue: Sass 2008,
9. There is another way in which Foucaults analysis 2009.
of Cervantes and Velasquez contradicts the standard
anti-humanist reading of his book. I noted that Don References
Quixote, written toward the end of the Renaissance
Delacampagne, C. 1995. Histoire de la philosophie au
(1605/15), is described as anticipating the looming
XXe sicle. Paris: Editions du Seuil.
Enlightenment episteme. Even more remarkable is the
Derrida, J. 1967a/1973. Speech and phenomena and
fact that Las Meninas, painted near the beginning of
other essays on Husserls theory of signs, trans. D. Al-
the Enlightenment (1656), seems to suggest an acute (if
lison. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
problematic) awareness of the lacuna of its own pre-
. 1967b/1978. Structure, sign, and play in the
sumed episteme, emblematized by the looming absence
discourse of the human sciences. In Writing and
of the royal viewers. Indeed, it is almost as if Velasquez
difference, trans. A. Bass, 35170. Chicago, IL:
were able, somehow, to look back on the Enlightenment
University of Chicago Press.
from the standpoint of the still-distant modern age,
Descombes, V. 1980. Modern French philosophy. Cam-
an era when the observers role will be more explicitly
bridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
acknowledged. In both cases we are presented with a
Descombes, V., and C. Larmore. 2009. Dernires nou-
work of art that is interpreted as transcending its own
velles du moi. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
episteme. Both analyses suggest that at least some per-
Duportail, G. F. 2013. Lorigine de la psychanalyse:
sons (only geniuses perhaps?) may indeed possess the
Introduction une phnomnologie de linconscient.
kind of intellectual freedom and reflective self-awareness
Paris: Mimesis.
340 PPP / Vol. 21, No. 4 / December 2014

Eribon, D. 1991. Michel Foucault, trans. B. Wing. and language in psychoanalysis. In crits: Complete
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. edition, trans. B. Fink, 197268. New York: Norton.
Fink, E. (1985/1995). Sixth Cartesian meditation: The . 1993. Seminar of Jacques Lacan: Book III, the
idea of a transcendental theory of method, trans. R. psychoses 19551956, trans. R. Grigg. New York:
Bruzina. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Norton.
Foucault, M. 1966/1994. The order of things. New . 1960/2006. The subversion of the subject and
York: Random House. dialectic of desire in the Freudian unconscious. In
. 1969/1972. The archaeology of knowledge, crits: complete edition, trans. B. Fink, 671702.
trans. A. M. S. Smith. New York: Pantheon. New York: Norton.
. 1975/1995. Discipline and punish, trans. A. . 1964/1977. Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book
Sheridan. New York: Vintage. XI: The four fundamental concepts of psychoanaly-
Gallagher, C. trans. 2002. Seminar of Jacques Lacan, sis, trans. A. Sheridan. New York: Norton.
Book XV, The psychoanalytic act 19671968. un- . 1966/2006 (orig presented 1949, orig publ
published, URL: http://www.tau.ac.il/~cohenron/ 1966). The mirror stage as formative of the I-
ScanSeminar.pdf function as revealed in psychoanalytic experience.
. 2010. A reading of the psychoanalytic act, In crits: complete edition, trans. B. Fink, 7581.
19671968. URL: http://www.lacaninireland.com/ New York: Norton.
web/wp-content/uploads/2010/06/Spring_2000-A- . 2007. Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book XVII,
READING-OF-THE-PSYCHOANALYTIC-ACT- The other side of psychoanalysis, trans. R. Grigg.
1967-1968-Cormac-Gallagher.pdf New York: Norton.
Gutting, G. 2001. French philosophy in the 20th century. Leguil, C. 2012. Sartre avec Lacan: Corrlation an-
Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press. tinomique, liaison dangereuse. Paris: Navarin/Le
Heidegger, M. 1927a/1996. Being and time, trans. J. Champ freudien.
Stambaugh. Albany: SUNY Press. Levi-Strauss, C. 1962/1966. The savage mind. Chicago:
. 1927b/1988. The basic problems of phenom- University of Chicago Press.
enology, trans. A. Hofstadter. Bloomington: Indiana Merleau-Ponty, M. 1945/2012. Phenomenology of per-
University Press. (lectures 1927 published in German ception, trans D. A. Landes. New York: Routledge.
in 1975) Miller, J-A. 1992. Seminar of Jacques Lacan: Book VII,
. 1949/2008. Letter on humanism. In Basic The ethics of psychoanalysis 19591960, trans. D.
writings, ed. D. F. Krell, 213266. London: Harper Porter. New York: Norton.
Perennial. . 2012. Prface. In Sartre avec Lacan, C. Leguil
. 1950/1971. Language. In Poetry, language, (author), 710. Navarin.
thought, trans A. Hofstadter, 185208. New York: Nancy, J-L. 2009. Interview with Jacques Derrida. The
Harper. Symptom 10, Spring. Available from: www.lacan.
. 1954/1956. Logos, trans. J. Lacan. La psych- com/thesymptom/?p=271
analyse, no. 1: 5979. (Delivered in 1953, published Phillips, J. 1996. Lacan and Merleau-Ponty: The con-
in German 1954). frontation of psychoanalysis and phenomenology.
. 1977. The question concerning technology and In Disseminating Lacan, ed. D. Pettigrew and F.
other essays, trans. W. Lovitt. New York: Harper Raffoul, 69108. Albany: SUNY Press.
and Row. Pluth, E. 2007. Signifiers and acts: Freedom in Lacans
Honderich, T. ed. 1995. The Oxford companion to theory of the subject. Albany: SUNY Press.
philosophy. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Presses Universitaires de France. 2013. tudes philos-
Husserl, E. 1913/1982. Ideas pertaining to a pure ophiques: Foucault et la phnomnologie 106, no.
phenomenology and to a phenomenological phi- 3:311422.
losophyFirst book, trans. F. Kersten. The Hague: Sass, L. l987. Schrebers panopticism: Psychosis and the
Nijhoff. modern soul. Social Research 54:l0l47.
. 1954/1970. The crisis of European sciences . 1992. Madness and modernism: Insanity in the
and transcendental phenomenology, trans. D. Carr. light of modern art, literature, and thought. New
Evanston IL: Northwestern University Press (written York: Basic Books.
1936, published in German 1954). . 1997. The consciousness machine: Self and
Lacan, J. 1953a. Le symbolique, limaginaire, et le subjectivity in schizophrenia and modern culture. In
rel. Bulletin interne de lAssociation franaise de The conceptual self in context, ed. U. Neisser and
psychanalyse, p. 413. D. Jopling, 20332. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
. 1953b/2006. The function and field of speech University Press.
Sass / Lacan, Foucault, and Crisis of the Subject 341

. 2001. The magnificent harlequin (book essay Strawson, P. F. 1959. Individuals: An essay in descriptive
on Jacques Lacan). International Journal of Psycho- metaphysics. London: Methuen.
analysis 82:9971018. Wicks, R. 2003. Modern French philosophy: From
. 2008. Michel Foucault and the contradictions existentialism to postmodernism. Oxford, UK:
of modern thought. Journal of Theoretical and Oneworld.
Philosophical Psychology 28:60113. Worms, F. 2009. La philosophie en France au XXe
. 2009. Foucault et lauto-reflxion moderne. sicle, moments. Paris: Gallimard.
(Foucault and modern self-reflection). Les Temps Zizek, S. 1990. For they know not what they do. Lon-
Modernes, 656:99143. (Paris; in French transla- don: Verso.
tion). . 1997/2005. The act and its vicissitudes. The
. In Press. Lacan: The mind of the modernist. Symptom. Available from: www.lacan.com/symp-
Continental Philosophy Review. tom6_articles/zizek.html
Sass, L., and E. Pienkos. 2013. Space, time, and atmo- . 1999. The superego and act [lecture]. Available
sphere: A comparative phenomenology of melan- from: www.egs.edu/faculty/slavoj-zizek/articles/the-
cholia, mania, and schizophrenia, Part II. Journal superego-and-the-act/
of Consciousness Studies 20:13152. . 2000. The ticklish subject: The absent center
Seigel, J. 2005. The idea of the self. New York: Cam- of political ontology. London: Verso.
bridge University Press.

You might also like