You are on page 1of 28

Copyright The British Psychological Society

Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

139

British Journal of Social Psychology (2008), 47, 139165 q 2008 The British Psychological Society

The British Psychological Society


www.bpsjournals.co.uk

In the ruins of representation: Identity, individuality, subjectication


Dimitris Papadopoulos*
School of Social Sciences, Cardiff University, UK
This paper explores a threefold shift in our understanding of identity formation and self-relationality: from an essentialist understanding of identity, to discursive and constructivist approaches, to, nally, the notion of embodied subjectication. The main target of this paper is to historicize these ideas and to localize them in the current social and political conditions of North-Atlantic societies. The core argument is that these three steps in reformulating the concept of identity correspond to an emerging form of subjectivity, afrmative subjectivity, which is bound to the proliferation of the post-Fordist reorganization of the social and political realm. The three theoretical shifts and their social situatedness will be illustrated through a rereading of some ideas from Lev S. Vygotskys late theory, Michel Foucaults account of government and Jacques ` Rancieres political philosophy.

One is too few, but two are too many Donna Haraway (1991b, p. 177)

Three accounts of identity


Identity usually has a double connotation: individual identity and identity politics. This distinction seems to rely on a widespread division of labour in social sciences. Psychology and behavioural sciences deal with individual processes of identity formation, while sociology and cultural studies explore social and cultural congurations of identity and their relevance for different communities and social institutions relying on these identities. The emergence of alternative theoretical accounts on identity has questioned this division. Identity politics presuppose a certain psychological apparatus and, concomitantly, processes of self-relationality and psychological identication require the organization of the sociopolitical space into discernible groups who maintain a feeling of belongingness and negotiate intensive relations to imagined cohesive
* Correspondence should be addressed to Dr Dimitris Papadopoulos, Cardiff University, School of Social Sciences, Glamorgan Building, King Edward VII Ave, Cardiff CF10 3WT, UK (e-mail: papadopoulosd@cardiff.ac.uk).
DOI:10.1348/014466607X187037

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

140 Dimitris Papadopoulos

communities (Anderson, 1991; Hall & du Gay, 1996). The proliferation of these alternative accounts of identity has challenged traditional essentialist understandings which consider identity to be a quality or a sum of qualities fastened as an abstract essence to the individual (e.g. Erikson, 1993; Marcia, 1993a; for a critical evaluation of these positions s. Kroger, 1996; Yoder, 2000). Alternative positions, in particular discursive and constructivist approaches, stress the social nature of identity as the outcome of interaction and positioning in different sociocultural contexts (e.g. Edwards, 1992; Gergen, 1990, 1997; Keupp, 1997; Shotter, 1993a). However, the turn from the essentialist to a constructivist understanding of identity, has been widely problematized as insufcient for tackling the issue of the individual/social dichotomy (Henriques, Hollway, Urwin, Venn, & Walkerdine, 1984; Parker, 1992; Teo, 2005). Critical psychology and critical social psychology challenge constructivist approaches on the grounds that they repeat the fallacy which they try to overcome, foundationalism. While traditional theory reduces identity to an individual substance (e.g. Erikson, 1993), constructivist approaches reduce identity to discursive positioning (e.g. Gergen, 1991). I will come to the differences between these two positions in the next sections of this paper, but for the moment I want to highlight one important similarity which is crucial for understanding the knowledge politics of identity. In both positions, we are dealing with an unspoken foundation underlying the process of identity formation. This is the notion of the self, the notion that there is a particular individual entity which is silently presupposed when we use the concept identity. As Charles Taylor (1989) suggests, the central core of the modern self arises from the feeling of an inner life in the individual. The modern individualistic image of the human being relies on this foundationalist person-centred understanding of the self. Stenner (2004) shows how this image of the human being serves as one of the foundations for the emergence of modern political rationality, and Fraser (1999) describes how reproductive heteronormativity is organized and sustained by the very idea of selfhood. This tight grip between political rationalities of government, sexuality and the psychological subject consolidates the self as the inescapable starting-point for every modern attempt to think the individual (Giddens, 1991). Neither essentialist nor constructivist positions seriously question the idea of the self; instead their main concern is to dene its origins. Are the origins of the self discursive or innate, dialogical or personal, relational or atomistic? As Harre (1983) says, a transcendental moment is implied when we speak about identity; a moment which presupposes the unity of the self in time and space through a certain hierarchy of action and consciousness. The self irrespective of its origins appears to be the bottom line and guarantor of identity (cf. Bruner, 1990). There are reasons that the category of the self remains unquestioned in both the positions. The reason is that in North-Atlantic societies we cannot think of the individual without the self. We are unable to think of the individual without something which maintains this very basic unity in space and time; and this is the self. The very core of psychology as science is rooted in this understanding of individuality (Danziger, 1997). But, for the purposes of this paper, that is to interrogate the knowledge politics of identity, it is important to highlight that the individualistic perspective on the self is not simply a theoretical construction but an active constructive force of our social reality. Hence, irrespective of the philosophical or psychological conceptualizations of the self, it is sustained by an extensive sociopolitical apparatus which organizes our everyday lives and experiences. It is so difcult, almost impossible, to imagine ourselves outside of the talk about the self in North-Atlantic societies today. Governmentality

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

141

studies that is the investigation of technologies of self conduct and the governance of human behaviour (Burchell, 1996; Dean, 1999; Rose, 1989) show how this individualistic understanding of the self organizes and sustains social relations around the logic of an autonomous and entrepreneurial individual in contemporary liberal societies. It would be farcical to think that by merely describing and explaining ourselves differently we could alter the individualistic tenor of psychological thought and research, let alone dispose of the fashions of our existence and self-understanding. And this is why constructivist understandings of identity were criticized; they explore different discursive congurations of the self, but cannot question its proliferation. Therefore, not only essentialist positions but also constructivist positions rely on the self which is inseparable for the formation of individuality in North-Atlantic societies. On these grounds the critical psychological programme of research questions the constructivist foundationalism of identity and envisages the insertion of a moment of critical reexivity (Parker, 2005) into the processes through which identities are produced. For example, Blackman and Walkerdine suggest (2001, p. 110): What we are arguing then is that the image of the human subject at the heart of psychological theorizing the autonomous subject is not simply one version of ourselves that we can choose to take on or discard at will. Instead, we live and embody this image, through the relations we take up to ourselves, in a complex way, one that cannot be reduced simply to the function of an individuals talk and accomplished social action. We are tied to this image of subjectivity through its immersion within and across a range of social and cultural practices that continually address us as if we were persons of a particular kind. [ : : : ] If we are to address the role of psychology in processes of subject formation, we need to investigate, rst, how a desired psy image is embedded across a range of social and discursive practices, and second, how this image is lived or embodied by subjects in their own techniques of self-understanding and transformation. This last move from constructivism to critical psychology enables a nal shift in our understanding of identity: by dutifully following governmentality studies, in particular the work of Nikolas Rose, critical psychology moves the focus from identity formation to power-infused processes of embodied subjectication (Rose, 1989, 1996b). The focus now turns to how each different individual performs her participation in asymmetrical social relations by actively changing her lived ways of being.

Overview of the argument and structure of the paper


The main objective of this paper is to historicize the shifts in our understanding of identity from the essentialist view of traditional approaches to a constructivist understanding to, nally, critical psychological theories on subjectication and the conditions of the production of the self. The paper examines the knowledge politics of identity; that is, it investigates the social dimensions and implications of these three conceptualizations of identity. I will treat these approaches to identity as situated knowledges (Haraway, 1988) and explore the sociopolitical contexts in which these approaches become operative. The main argument is that the movement through these three steps in our conceptualization of identity corresponds to an emergent form of subjectivity which is situated in the ongoing neoliberal reorganization of the social realm since the 1970s. Paraphrasing one of the pioneering studies in the critical tradition of investigating the knowledge politics of psychological research, Walkerdines (1984, p. 189) work on Piaget, we can say that the radical intentions of these three theories on identity and the rectitude of their object do not matter; we have to make a distinction

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

142 Dimitris Papadopoulos

between the radical intentions of these theories and the effects and workings of these theories at a particular historical moment. Hence, if we take seriously the claim that theories of identity are situated knowledges and understand how psychology fabricates the social subjectivities which it studies, then we have to explore how newer alternative theories on identity that is constructivist and critical psychological positions are germane to the formation of new forms of social and political subjectivity in our societies. I will summarize these various forms of subjectivity under the concept of afrmative subjectivity. The characteristic feature of this form of subjectivity is that it shores up current forms of domination by the very fact that it is in the position to explore their conditions of production. In other words, the very fact that we are able to reect on and even to question our own active involvement in current structures of domination becomes the means through which contemporary domination is operating; and this is the sense in which the subjectivity which arises from these situated knowledges is afrmative. Afrmative denotes the fact that this form of subjectivity underpins what it questions. Thus, this paradoxical afrmative function of the alternative accounts on identity is a performative one: by challenging prevalent modes of subjectication and by investigating their situated and embodied realizations, these accounts create an action which corresponds to an emerging form of social relation pertinent to the malignance of neoliberal power (Papadopoulos, 2002). The reason for this is that alternative accounts have been primarily formulated as elements of resistance to the dominance of essentialism. However, after Foucault, we know that resistance strengthens what it tries to oppose. Alternative accounts are good for encompassing certain facets of domination and for initiating resistance, but cannot instigate real passages and cannot engage, in the words of Deleuze and Guattari (1987, p. 531), with cutting edges of creation and deterritorialization. The main rationale of this paper is to investigate this paradoxical function of constructivist and critical accounts of identity. The paradox is that the alternative accounts came into being as critiques of existing forms of domination, and, in fact, they are still able to function in this way on many occasions. However, from the perspective of the changing constitution of political and social power in NorthAtlantic societies, which I will describe in the last sections of this paper, alternative accounts to identity seem to sustain what they try to defy. As Wallerstein (1998, p. 13) says, the revolutions never worked the way their proponents hoped or the way their opponents feared. I will trace the emergence and solidication of afrmative subjectivity by examining the conceptual shifts made in the movements between the three theoretical positions on identity. The rst move, questioning an essentialist understanding of identity, will be approached by discussing Lev Vygotskys psychology (Part III). The reason for choosing Vygotsky is that his work has been widely deployed as a vehicle for overcoming essentialist and individualistic positions in psychology since the 1970s (of course there are also other theories which were used to achieve similar goals, but this is beyond the scope of this paper). In this part of the paper, I will assert that the break with essentialism is founded on the possibility of articulating the self: articulation refers to both enunciative practices of the person and the subjective rearrangement of existing meanings of her environment. I will then go on to show how a very specic reading of Vygotsky enabled the constructivist understanding of identity. This particular reading excluded other possible understandings of Vygotsky, those primarily developed in the eld of the German critical psychology and to a certain extent also in Soviet activity theory. In a second step (Part IV), I will refer to some ideas of Foucault which will help to understand how the

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

143

constructivist account on identity formation constitutes a form of self-government in the political realities since the 1970s. Critical psychology adds to these constructivist understandings the possibility of questioning the very conditions of the production of identity and by doing this arrives at the concept of embodied subjectication. Simultaneously and paradoxically, it contributes to the installation of afrmative subjectivity which will be discussed in Part V. In this part of the paper, I will explore how afrmative subjectivity constitutes the psychopolitical apparatus of the neoliberal subject in post-Fordist conditions. In the conclusion (Part VI), I will give a brief overview of the possible ways to interrupt the fabrication of afrmative subjectivity.

L.S. Vygotsky and the move from the essentialist to the constructivist conceptualization of identity
The essentialist understanding of identity tries to establish a systematic operational system which ascribes specic attributes to each particular individual. The statistical treatment of quantied human differences is a powerful tool for organizing and managing wide social and institutional landscapes (Kvale, 1977). From a knowledge politics perspective, understanding identity as an essence corresponds with the emergence of a social technology managing and steering the passage of people from one social institution to another: education, employment, family, etc. Consider, for example, the idea of developmental tasks which has been so inuential in theories of life-span development and identity formation (Havighurst, 1972). The main tenets of this theory are almost a mirror image of the expectations administration holds of what the subject needs to accomplish in the course of his/her lifelong development in order to facilitate the smooth operation of social institutions. As argued by many, the relationship between psychological theories, social policy and public administration is a closed circuit (e.g. White, 1996). All attempts to question essentialist theories of identity have started by insisting that the domain in which subjects interpret their experiences and adjust their action is, in effect, a network of meanings and practices which are particular to specic social contexts (Bruner, 1990; Geertz, 1973; Gergen & Gergen, 2002; Shweder, 1991). The starting-point for questioning essentialist notions of identity was to infuse an ambivalence into the very core of identity formation of the particular subject. Constructivist positions suggested that this core does not exist at all; it is made of the various ways each subject interprets and makes sense of meanings and artefacts in her context. If the essentialist understanding of identity assumes that identity formation unfolds along a predened set of stages and meanings (e.g. Marcias identity statuses, Marcia, 1993b; cf. the critique of Cote, 1996), its critics assert that there is an indeterminate relationship between the self and the meanings or artefacts surrounding a particular person (Bruner, 1995; Schraube, 1998). These critics widely assume that meanings and artefacts are the devices or cultural tools used in creating relations to the self and to others (Scarry, 1985). Here, it is worth emphasizing that these devices exist as soon as they are installed in the manifold self-governing techniques and practices of individuals (Bourdieu, 1990). Thus, from the viewpoint of psychological research on identity, cultural meanings and artefacts do not have pre-eminence over subjects, they are invented and realized by subjects (Marvakis & Papadopoulos, 2002). However, simply classifying and recording the meanings prevalent in a specic context does not provide direct evidence about the identity of a concrete real person. Therefore, even if drawing on culturalhistorical anthropology (e.g. Wulf, 2004) and

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

144 Dimitris Papadopoulos

cultural psychology (e.g. Cole, 1996; Wertsch, 1991) was important for introducing this fundamental ambivalence into the heart of essentialist accounts of identity, it was not enough to encompass the role of the individuals psychology in a non-essentialist process of identity formation. In other words, linking culture to identity is a helpful move towards questioning essentialism but does not necessarily enable an understanding of how individual subjectivity functions in relation to identity (a good example of this limitation can be found in the identity capital model which goes as far as developing scales for measurement of the culture-identity link s. Cote, 1997, 2000). Undertaking a cultural history or genealogy of networks of meaning does not, in and of itself, resolve questions as to how any given subject is related to these meaning networks. There is here a ne difference between the existing meanings of a discourse and the way individuals employ and use these meanings in their everyday lives. This difference is particularly tricky to conceptualize because meanings do not exist unless they are used by the actors of a certain social system (Luhmann, 1995). In addition, social actors cannot use meanings which are fully private, since this would lead to the break down of any communication (cf. the case against private language, Searle, 1995; Wittgenstein, 1958). Hence, the ne difference is that social meaning and individual meaning are irreversibly linked together and yet they are not identical. There is no direct correspondence between individual and social meaning, it is rather a constant and intimate relation of difference. If we follow this idea stringently, we have to then formulate a conceptual grid by which we would be able to trace the creation of individual differences in cultural meanings. In other words, what is of importance here is that cultural meanings are not identical for everyone but are subjectively appropriated and employed in the individuals everyday life. This turn to subjective meaning was the major theoretical shift initiated by various alternative psychological theories outside the UK in the 1970s and 1980s: from the subjects point of view, discursive meanings and practices can only be understood as subjective meanings and practices, that is, as my meanings and practices (Holzkamp, 1996). German critical psychology, for example, acknowledges the importance of the different contexts for the constitution of individuality, starts, however, not from the context itself neither from a core idea of the self but from the process of the subjective appropriation of a particular context (Holzkamp, 1983). This is the turn to subjectivity, the turn to understand individuality from the standpoint of the subject (Holzkamp, 1992). And here we have to highlight that the standpoint of the subject is obviously always different, it is always particular for each individual. Subjectivity according to critical psychology is always bound to the meanings and conditions of existence but it is not identical to them; rather, it is a relation of possibility to the existing meanings and conditions (Holzkamp, 1991). The turn to subjectivity asserts that if we want to understand identity in contemporary societies we have to decipher the processes involved in the production of subjective meaning. Any attempt to explain identity simply by doing a genealogy of the production of meaning in a certain institutional or sociocultural context is unable to engender an understanding of the creation of subjectivity. Thus, instead of interrogating the fabrication of cultural meanings the turn to subjectivity focuses on the exploration of subjective sense. By adopting the concept of sense I have turned to Vygotskys ideas. The differentiation between sense and meaning which Vygotsky introduced into his theory in the later years of his life (Vygotsky, 1934) refers directly to the theme of

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

145

self-articulation; that is, nding a voice by altering the given balance and content of the existing symbolic systems. He claims that the meaning enclosed in words is not a constant and unchangeable magnitude, but an available potency, which becomes material in the literal meaning of the word through its subjective application (s. chapter IV in Papadopoulos, 1999). He thus denes the possibility of the creation of the non-identical. Meanings only exist, that is they become real, when they are used by the subject. And the subjects use of meanings is a matter of constantly altering what has been given in the symbolic. Psychological identity is thus never identical with itself; it can be neither readable as a core psychic structure of the individual nor is it reducible to the meanings existing in the discourses of a certain sociocultural context. Rather, psychological identity is the constant oscillation between subjective sense and discursive meanings. The resemblances between Vygotskys and Wittgensteins (Wittgenstein, 1958) theoretical positions are obvious. They both attack the objectivistic nomological thought of traditional philosophy and traditional psychology. Wittgenstein had spoken about the subliminal otherness, about the non-identical in language construction (cf. also Wellmer, 1991) and Vygotsky tried to show how the non-identical in language is central to the psychological constitution of the subject (thus, challenging traditional accounts of identity). Both of them arrive at a similar thesis: the spoken word and objectied experience are not aspects or dimensions of meaning, they realize meaning. However, each of them investigates this assumption in different ways: Wittgenstein from the perspective of the construction of meaning and Vygotsky from the viewpoint of the individual. For Vygotsky, an utterance is steadily constituted by the existence of an unrealized otherness: all of which remain invisible, marginal, strictly personal, oppressed and nally unsayable. What is particularly fascinating in Vygotskys account is that this unrealized otherness is not rooted somewhere outside the utterance itself, as for example the unconscious in psychoanalytic approaches or some hidden innate mechanism in nativist accounts, or, nally, a social reference in theories of socialization. For Vygotsky unrealized otherness is simply an inherent feature of thinking and speech. It is the result of their immanent unfolding. Thought is never complete and is never exhausted in language. Thought is the affection of our bodies rather than the mere usage of semiotic means (Vygotskij, 1996). When Vygotsky (1934, p. 281) says that thought is always something whole, something with signicantly greater extent and volume than the individual word, and that what is contained simultaneously in thought unfolds sequentially in speech, he refers to the integrative power of subjective sense to unite the sayable with the unsayable. My utterances are what I am, but what I am is more than what you hear. Subjective sense exceeds the possibility of an objective conceptualization in theory and research because cognitive, volitional and emotional aspects, which cannot be isolated as distinguishable features of subjective experience, converge in it (Fichtner, 1996; Papadopoulos, 1999; Vygotsky, 1934). Vygotsky rmly rejects any possibility of an essentialist treatment of the constitution of the subject based on the operationalization of various elements of consciousness (at least in his late works, since Wygotski, 1930). The only chance for a humanization of psychology, according to Vygotsky, is to replace the inhuman concepts we usually deploy in academic psychology with human ones by returning to the everyday and the concrete (Wygotski, 1931, p. 146). Returning to the concrete means for Vygotsky to look for psychology in the actual realization of each individual in the irreversible passage of lived time. Here we can trace great resemblances between Vygotskys theory and process philosophy, especially Bergsons (Bergson,

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

146 Dimitris Papadopoulos

2001; Middleton & Brown, 2005, chapter 4) and Whiteheads (Kraus, 1998; Whitehead, 1979) understanding of experience as irreducibly linked to the immediate actuality of our existence. For Vygotsky, foregrounding the concrete, the irreducible totality of the psychological facts incorporated in subjective sense, means dismissing all metapsychological attempts to clearly delineate and differentiate psychological processes. It means returning to everyday subjectivity, a desideratum which Vygotsky formulates, following Politzer (1929), by postulating the necessity of treating individual existence as a drama (Vygotsky, 1929); that is, as a concrete subjective action in the midst of controversial, dilemmatic social conditions (Hildebrand-Nilshon & Kim, 2002; Hildebrand-Nilshon, ` Motzkau, & Papadopoulos, 2001; Seve, 1977). After all, human beings not only develop, they construct themselves (Vygotsky, 1929, p. 65). And this construction, understood as self-government, occurs in moments where the self is produced through the subjective reorganization of discursive practices and meanings. In contrast to widespread constructivist readings of Vygotsky (cf. Chapter III.7 in Papadopoulos, 1999), which suggest that governing the self is an effect of discourse, the reading I am offering here holds that governing the self amounts to the insertion of subjective that is unique biographical, affective and situational components into the meanings of the discourse. Conducting the self in Vygotskys psychology means realizing subjective sense in an intersubjective situation, or better, it means the effort to transform the unsayable totality of thought into a sayable communicative articulation. This attempt positions the subject in a concrete argumentative and contentious context in which used meanings acquire their importance and relevance for the individual insofar as they can be transformed into subjective sense. Thus, being positioned in a discursive practice entails subordination to the rules and contents which make the discourse sustainable and available for the participants, but at the same moment it also entails self-articulation, that is the creation of new interdependences between the self and others. This is the process of individuation (in Vygotskys terms this is the primacy of inter over intra), a process of non-personal becoming, a process where the common and pre-individual social reality becomes gradually the ground out of which the singularity of the one occurs. The understanding of the individual here is very different from its meaning in theories of the autonomous self. Autonomy promotes individual freedoms and the cultivation of individuality (Rose, 1996a). In contrast, individuation promotes singularity, enriching what is already common, infusing social relations in the core of the singular self (Simondon, 1992; Stephenson & Papadopoulos, 2006). Vygotsky captures this moment with his concept of inner speech (our inner, elliptic, soundless, only partly formalized speaking). Inner speech is the means through which subjectivity is realized. It is the reection of reection, in other words the conduct of conduct. And since subjectication is a process situated in discursive practices, inner speech simultaneously involves the reproduction of discursive meanings and the liberation from these. Inner speech is, as argued by Holzkamp (1996, p. 62), implicit intersubjectivity in terms of its function for subjective experiences (Bradley, 2005) as well as in a developmental perspective (Selby & Bradley, 2003). The reading of Vygotsky which I presented in the previous paragraphs could very much pertain to an understanding of the subject in German critical psychology tradition, especially the work of Klaus Holzkamp (1993), and it could be also relevant to some versions of activity theory (partly in Leontjew, 1977; and also in Rubinstein, 1977). However, there is a second interpretation of Vygotskys work which leads to a very

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

147

different constitution of individuality and the self: the dissolution of individual subjectivity in discourse. This second reading is particularly central for understanding how the move out of essentialism bypassed the German or some Soviet readings of Vygotsky and gave birth to the discursive/constructivist approaches to identity and subjectivity which came to dominate Anglocentric non-mainstream psychology (Billig, 1996; Gergen, 1994; Gill, 2006; Potter & Wetherell, 1987; Shotter, 1993b; Wetherell, 1996). This reading ignores Vygotskys account of the role of subjective self-articulation and individuation and understands subjectivity as a discursive effect. Here, the subject is recast as a discourse user and identities are variations tied to particular subject positions (Davies & Harre, 1990) which emerge out of the deployment of the existing interpretative repertoires (Billig, 1991; Wetherell, 1998). If we reconsider the move from an essentialist understanding of identity to the constructivist position, we can see how the sense/meaning tension, the process of implicit intersubjectivity and nally the process of self-articulation/individuation give way to the idea that identity is primarily constituted through discourse and language (for a more detailed discussion of the problem and the ambiguities of Anglocentric discursive psychology s. Stenner, 2005). According to this position, identity means occupying one of the many various language positions existing in discourse. Here the subject is tentatively identical with his/her specic sociolinguistic placement, while in Vygotskys account the subject can never be identical with the social and with language. As Seymour-Smith, Wetherell, and Phoenix (2002, p. 255) say: Common to discursive and social constructionist research (Gergen, 1994; Riessman, 1993) is the claim that identity (personhood) is constituted and reconstituted through discourse and is thus exible, contextual, relational, situated and inected by power relations. Davies and Harre argue that who one is always an open question with a shifting answer depending on the positions made available through talk, in interaction and conversations. The storylines of everyday conversations provide us with a position to speak from and they allow the positioning of others as characters with roles and rights. For Vygotsky, the subject incorporates the wholeness of the contradictions entailed in discourse. The subject is genuinely singular and different to herself, since she can never reproduce a particular social position through her language expressions. Subjectivity is embodied otherness, identity is impossible (Irigaray, 1985). This position brings me to my next consideration and shift in the conceptualization of identity, one which not only tries to overcome the language-centred and discursive foundationalism of constructivist approaches but also the concept of identity as such (it is not a coincidence that in the German and Soviet readings of Vygotsky the concept of identity plays a minor role). This shift, described in the following section, reconsiders identity as embodied subjectication.

Foucault and the move from a constructivist understanding of identity to embodied subjectication
The modes by which we relate to ourselves through our connections to our social context could be understood as processes of subjectication. According to the classic Foucauldian denition, subjectication means examining the ways in which a person transforms himself or herself into a subject (Foucault, 1994a). Notably, this conceptualization of the subject in late Foucault is opposed to the abstract idea of the philosophical subject (that is, a subject dened in advance by certain characteristics which predetermine the results of any empirical investigation of real subjects

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

148 Dimitris Papadopoulos

and anticipate the theoretical outcomes). The philosophical subject is a logical construction conceived by means of a series of archetypical or substantial denitions: the intentional, transcendental, decentred, saturated, deconstructed, integrative, autonomous and so on. There is a great deal of work in psychology, sociology and social theory which has contributed in deconstructing this philosophical conceptualization of the subject (e.g. Bauman, 1997; Butler, 1990; Cadava, Connor, & Nancy, 1991; Middleton & Brown, 2005; Shotter & Gergen, 1989). Their main critique is that the philosophical subject has an intrinsic logic or better, an inherent purpose which would or should be exemplied in every different person. The subject is understood to be intact, consistent and separable from the continuous inuences of the real, social conditions of her existence. There is another way of speaking about the subject, albeit which still shows the same bias as the philosophical one. This way can be derived from a specic sociological reading of the writings of Foucault on power, especially in his work around the mid1970s. In this reading, the subject is mainly conceived as the object of the discourse. The prerequisites of a philosophical foundation of the subject are replaced with the strict dominance of disciplinary technologies. Foucault shows this in his discussion of the role of confession in the 1st Volume of History of Sexuality (Foucault, 1978) or of the individualizing and subjugating function of surveillance technologies in Discipline and Punish (Foucault, 1977). Working with this sociological understanding of the subject entails elucidating the conceptual, analytic edice of specic discourses in order to formulate the signifying links which constitute and regulate the individual subject. Foucault would rather speak of the subject-function in a specic discourse rather than subjects of discourses (Foucault, 1984). The constructivist conceptualization of identity, described above, draws on this sociological understanding of Foucault. The problem with this reading of Foucault, and with an understanding of identity as social positioning in dilemmatic discursive contexts, is that it is language-centred and relies heavily on the investigation of existing representations circulating in discourse. The constructivist approach to identity locates subjective identity as the product of the ambiguities and controversies of discursive practices. But it fails to recognize that there is more to subjectivity, an excess which pertains to forms of social imagination which are beyond existing representations, which are affective, contentious and not yet realized in nature. Bradley makes a similar point in relation to the Theory of Mind which suppress their own imaginative and moral dimensions (Bradley, 1993, p. 515), and others turn to psychoanalysis to insert this lost perspective of indeterminacy in discourse (Billig, 1997). Instead of solely focusing on existing representations of what is needed is rather, as Boaventura de Sousa Santos (2001, p. 191) calls it, a sociology of absences, a procedure through which what does not exist, or whose existence is socially ungraspable or inexpressible, is conceived of as the active result of a given social process. Doing discursive analysis and constructivist research on identity are as dry as the Anglocentric empiricist tradition in social psychology can be. This is because they perpetuate the cult of empiricism in social science research which conceives the investigation of existing representations be it in qualitative or quantitative form as the primary starting-point for the generation of knowledge (cf. various critiques of this: Groeben, 2006; Holzkamp, 1987; Smedslund, 1988; Tolman, 1991; Toulmin & Leary, 1985). And we cannot afford this in our current conditions where identities are played out, not just as social positions, but as effective and powerful tools which organize social and cultural processes of dominance inside North-Atlantic societies as well as on a geopolitical scale. For future generations, the

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

149

xation on linguistic processes and discourse, this widespread bizarre belief of our times, as Hayles calls it (1999, p. 199), will probably appear as a superstition (cf. Papadopoulos, 2005). Here I want to assert that it is possible to question the imperative to use discursive representations as hard empirical data and engage with them as one of the many tools available for undertaking strategic politics in a situated process of political action and engagement. As Donna Haraway says, language is not about description but about commitment (Haraway, 1991a, p. 214; cf. also Haraway, 1988). Without being able to introduce the possibility of making discursive analysis itself the object of study that is understanding ones own research practice as a situated cultural and political practice discursive/constructivist positions can only reproduce the content of the existing representations under study and perpetuate the conditions of their production. Adorno (1983) describes such a situation as the fabrication of everthe-same. Discursive foundationalism forecloses any possibility of understanding how contested identities emerge as concrete everyday processes of materialization of imagined social relations. Discourse analysis cannot deal with something which is not already represented in discourse. And, as cultural studies have so vividly showed that identity is always in the making because it entails a non-expressed otherness, a nondiscursied and imagined possibility of social relations (Hall, 1990; Papadopoulos, 2006). This is particularly important during the post-war period where identity politics occupy a central place in the political life of North-Atlantic societies. We need a different conceptualization of subjectication and identity in order to understand the strengths and limitations of identity politics, as well as their inner-workings how people identify with certain imagined cultural communities and groups of civil society in order to account for the immanent, eventful (Badiou, 2001) and uid, strategic nature (Clifford, 2000) of subjectication and identity politics in contemporary societies. This immanent and strategic emergence of identity always and necessarily entails a moment of suddenness (Bohrer, 1998), a non-existent reorganization of the material and discursive conditions of existence. Any account which fails to grapple with the contingent, nonidentical elements of identity, not only reies its subject matter, but offers a static and limited picture of identity as a political tool. Already in the 1970s and 1980s, cultural studies and gender studies identied this as a limitation of existing concepts of identity. In response, they focused on the process of articulation (Clifford, 2001; Hall, 1986a; Slack, 1996). Articulation attempts to rethink the concept of Gramscian hegemony as a necessary element of the discursive reductionism of many post-structuralist approaches to everyday cultural politics (Laclau & Mouffe, 1985). The very idea of gender studies is based on the project of contesting gender normativity and heterosexist dominance by rendering the symbolic increasingly dynamic, that is, by considering the conditions and limits of representation and representability as open to signicant rearticulations and transformations under the pressure of social practices of various kinds (Butler, 1997, p. 23). Similarly, the very idea of cultural studies (as well as science studies, s. Latour, 2004) is based on reworking the opaque and resistant notion of ideology into something increasingly exible and transformable through politics of hegemony: Thus, a theory of articulation is both a way of understanding how ideological elements come, under certain conditions, to cohere together within a discourse, and a way of asking how they do or do not become articulated, at specic conjunctures, to certain political subjects. Let me put that the other way: the theory of articulation asks how an ideology discovers its subject rather than how the subject thinks the necessary and inevitable thoughts which belong to it; it enables us to think how an ideology empowers people, enabling them to begin to

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

150 Dimitris Papadopoulos

make some sense or intelligibility of their historical situation, without reducing those forms of intelligibility to their socio-economic or class location or social position (Hall, 1986b, p. 53). The reinsertion of politics of articulation as hegemonic politics into the constitution of identity corresponds to an alternative second reading of Foucault (opposed to the sociological one described in the beginning of this section) which reintroduces an important element of Vygotskys interest in sense/meaning and inner speech: that is, it reminds us that when we speak about identity we have then to presuppose that the individual is not exhausted in the signifying practices which he/she employs. Identity cannot be conceived without a constitutive outside which surpasses existing meanings and practices in the discourse. To put it another way, identity corresponds continuously with a prescriptive lack: a lack consisting of unanswered or unperceived possibilities for relating to the self and the other possibilities which have never been realized. Identity is a closure, an exclusion, an attachment to a specic spatialized position only because it can be so and not because it has to be so. Thus, the employment of an identity does not necessarily regulate or overdetermine the individuals existence, but positions the subject in the tension between coercion by institutional mechanisms (meanings and practices) and articulation through them. In the theories following this second reading of Foucault articulation has a double meaning: pronouncing subjective experience and connecting and reconnecting existing meanings in ways which were not presented before (Hall, 1986b, 1990). Hence, when the self-governed subject adopts identity, this move can be understood as a relation between empowerment and subjugation to political practices of liberal societies, between taking on meanings as they are and reworking meanings with new content and with new practices. It would be a mistake to claim that the cultural studies interest in articulation as a means of theorizing identity is simply Foucauldian (Hall, 1996), I have been suggesting that it relates to a second reading of Foucault, a reading which I want to briey consider. Starting in the mid-1970s, Foucault began to introduce an idea of subjectication as a tool for grappling with the possibility that subjects encounter not only ruptures in discourse, but also opportunities to render these ruptures intelligible by questioning the paralysing solidity of power mechanisms (Foucault, 1990, 1987). The ruptures are interrogated in Foucaults turn to the subject in the last years of his life; he examines all these shady, intermittently shifting possibilities for modifying the conditions of visibility in a given discourse, ruptures which give rise to doubts about the prearranged, persistent borders of existing practices (Deleuze, 1991). This turn is in step with a well-known transformation of Foucaults understanding of power. The earlier notion of power was that power is a monistic entity penetrating, contaminating, prescribing and nally regulating individual existence through the inescapable force of disciplinary mechanisms. This is gradually replaced by a view of power as functioning through the open control and self-control of each individual. Power is much more disseminated in various individualizing modalities, which could be described as the government techniques of self-enterprising individuals (Foucault, 1994c, 1988). The concept of government rests on the idea that power can be grasped only as a communicative, intersubjective practice based on existing societal constraints and conditions, and thus means acting upon present or coming actions in order to facilitate or to nullify possible relationships to others (Foucault, 1994b). Government involves both acting upon others and acting upon the self, and in this sense, it can be comprehended as the various social rationalities and practices entailed when individuals

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

151

employ strategies for the conduct of conduct (Rose, 1996a). Government dispenses with the restrictive notion of individual existence as coerced through various disciplinary and regulatory mechanisms for exercising power, since it implicitly introduces liberty as the constitutive outside of the subject. Here, liberty means the freedom for self-enterprising; freedom as a stable number of possibilities through which individuals exercise power. Power can only be accomplished by free subjects. Hence, as Foucault reworks his understanding of power, there is a shift taking place away from the question of how individuals identity is constructed. Rather Foucault is interested in how individuals become subjects of a certain kind, that is how they relate to themselves and to each other. These relationships are sustained by existing socially fabricated meanings and practices, which achieve their relevance for each subject only if they are actively used by the individual for conducting and managing everyday life. For example, Foucault describes these technologies of the self extensively in the 2nd Volume of History of Sexuality when he investigates how ones ethics and social relations are shaped by the everyday sexual practices in ancient Greece (Foucault, 1987). How can we combine an account about different discursive formations and modes of social government with an account about the ways individuals freely realize these modes of government in their everyday lives in order to maintain the relation of self to self and of self to others? How can we avoid the pitfalls of reproducing the idea of a mere regulation of the individuals, namely by asserting that individual government is shaped in a process of inscription of discourses? This move against and away from the constructivist approach to identity has been supported by the critical psychological concept of subjectication or, rather, embodied subjectication (e.g. Blackman & Walkerdine, 2001; Burman, 1994; Rose, 1996a). Working with Foucaults later approach to power and government involves examining how specic practices and techniques operate with and beyond language and create possibilities for the production of particular forms of embodied experience (Blackman, 2000; Dean, 1995; Kelly, 2006; Walkerdine, 1997). On the one hand, this work investigates different representations of subjectivity within current cultural and media production. On the other hand, it explores how these representations become embodied through relational and situated practices of the subjects. Here it is important to stress that embodiment does not refer to materiality (Papadopoulos, 2005). Rather, it designates all these techniques which situate the individual body in discourse. That is how one performs her position in discourse through her body, that is through particular movements, gestures, body modications, habits of the esh, ways to talk and body accessories. The central focus of embodied subjectication is how discourse is realized by each one of us through our bodies. Using the words of Karen Barad, we could say that critical psychology is interested in how discourse comes to matter and, in taking this approach, it neglects important and difcult questions about how matter comes to matter (Barad, 1998). In this sense, critical psychology reads the materiality of the body solely as a semiotic battleeld and remains committed to embodiment as a pure question of representation (Csordas, 1994, 1999). If the discursive/constructivist notion of identity was always in discussion with identity politics, embodied subjectication and the critical psychological approach operate on the level of (and invigorate) micropolitical participation in social and political processes. Micropolitics involve: (1) engaging with processes of representation; (2) investing in the moment of reexivity as the possibility for questioning the conditions of production of ones own subjectivity; (3) using embodied activity as the performative realization of existing representations and (4)

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

152 Dimitris Papadopoulos

prioritizing relational modes of conduct, that is relations between individuals or actants. For example, the analysis of micropractices through which HIV-positive gay men forge a relation to Anti-Retroviral Treatment illustrates how people adjust to the immediate necessities posed by the treatment regimens by organizing a myriad of social interactions beyond institutionalized regulation and xed representations (for an extensive discussion of these examples s. Stephenson & Papadopoulos, 2006). Although, there may be a common desire to respond to the expectation that people take charge of treatments, the differentiated practices entailed in peoples responses can open starkly different modes of relating to the self and to others. A focus on micropractices reveals how all these different modes of subjectication unfold in realms which are not hierarchically driven by health policies, by clinical management agenda or by psychological discourses of control. The embodiment of personal control is related to, but not determined by these sites. For example, being in charge can act as a vehicle for a new trajectory into employment and work. In other moments, it can require the renegotiation of ones relation to biomedical authority. Alternatively, there are modes of relating to the imperative to take charge which question the very possibility of that goal. New embodied subjectivities emerge through differential relationship to representations of risk (Kippax & Race, 2003; Race, 2001). The real possibilities being opened by biomedical advances in HIV treatments force a move beyond any blanket criticism of biomedicine, beyond the separation of medical and social domains of life. In this move, people reconstitute themselves in relation to biomedicine, realizing possibilities for sociopolitical change not through resistance to institutional or biomedical authority but through actively organizing and reorganizing their relation to all the various actors in the social eld. In the power relations of the post-Anti-Retroviral Treatment chronotope, there is no one privileged subject imposing a dominant mode of sociality. There is a network consisting of different actants for example, pills, doctors, patients, tests, pharmaceutical companies, state institutions, community organizations and activists (Flowers, 2001; Rosengarten, 2004). The ongoing transformations in the connections between nodes in this network open new possibilities for living with HIV and close others. Thus, the process through which change and contemporary everyday sociability occurs cannot be understood as principally driven by state legislation and policy but through the micropolitical practices of embodied subjectication. Hence, micropolitics purposively work against the logic that posits the state (or other grand institutions) as the genesis of sociopolitical change and of the subsequent production of subjectivity (e.g. Connolly, 2002). Critical psychology has contributed to this reconsideration of the relation between state policies and everyday sociality. Instead of positing a hierarchical relation between the state and the social sphere, critical psychology explores how embodied subjectivities emerge in the action of multiple, networked, acentrically organized agents that is, the state is no longer understood as a privileged entity of power. Now, instead of emanating from monolithic state institutions, subjectivity is located in the relations between multiple actants involved in diversied and often informal networks which perform and pursue different interests and political agenda. In this section, I described the turn from constructivist understandings of identity to the critical psychological concept of embodied subjectication as a particular form of political practice in contemporary North-Atlantic societies. In the next part of the paper, I will explore the historical and social situatedness of this critical psychological turn to micropolitics and embodied subjectication and trace its involvement in the production of afrmative subjectivity.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

153

Micropolitics and the persistence of afrmative subjectivity in post-Fordist conditions


The turn to micropolitics and the dissolution of the foundationalist understandings of identity (either in its essentialist or discursive reductionist versions) enable political analyses of previously neglected and effaced domains of everyday life. But do micropolitics effectively challenge state regulation and open pathways for the emergence of a multiplicity of different modes of embodied subjectication? Or does embodied subjectication become a new mode of state regulated existence? The power of micropolitics is thought to lie in the fact that they bypass the reproduction of the state as an intact and paramount entity of power. Micropolitics harness everyday lived and embodied experience as a vital matter of political struggles which aim to reinvigorate civil society, that is, the struggles of associations of people which develop outside of state institutions (Warner, 2002). However, seen historically, since the 1980s micropolitics have increasingly become integral to the effective realization of neoliberal governance. This is because this mode of engagement is aligned with transformations which have occurred at the level of the state. The neoliberal state is not a monolithic container, rather it disseminates into the most remote terrains of everyday experience. The dismantling of welfare systems has accelerated, and nally consolidated, the states withdrawal from the traditional role of centralized organizer of society. However, the result has not been the disappearance of the state itself, rather we are witnessing the disappearance of the welfare state and the emergence of new one (Fairbrother & Rainnie, 2005; Jessop, 2002; Sassen, 1999). Social control is primarily performed through the colonization of previously regarded private areas of individual existence: the body, health, fashion and well-being, sexuality, your living-room. In this process, embodied subjectication and micropolitics have become necessary elements for the functioning of the neoliberal state. The neoliberal state needs, more than selfregulating individuals, networked actors who actively forge the structures necessary for the transformation from centralized state powers to disseminated modes of neoliberal regulation (Marazzi, 1998; Neilson & Rossiter, 2005; Papadopoulos, 2003; Stephenson, 2003). Hence, although they arose as an attempt to challenge the overly narrow focus on the state, micropolitics have played a vital role in shifting the historical function of the state from centralized control into a disseminated form of control which operates effectively in the terrain of social and cultural life. In this sense, both state- and micropolitics articulate their political agenda inside the terrain of the state and afrm its function and centrality in social life. This is the moment where embodied subjectication and the broader project of critical psychology amplify the production of afrmative subjectivity, a subjectivity which paradoxically solidies state regulation by operating at its margins. However, the generation of afrmative subjectivity is more than a form of political regulation in contemporary North-Atlantic societies. It is also a productive force in the literal sense. The traditional apparatus for measuring and diagnosing individual differences was insufcient as a response to the social and economical transformations related to post-Fordist labour (Bowring, 2002; Gorz, 2004; Lazzarato, 2002; Moulier Boutang, 2003; Williams, 1994). This is because post-Fordism appropriates as productive resources precisely these forms of individual action and experience, which refer to the totality of individual subjectivity: relationality, emotions, memory, communication, creativity and primarily, the totality of the body. Critical psychologys conceptualization captures the core tenet of the post-Fordist transformation in a

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

154 Dimitris Papadopoulos

magnicent way: embodied subjectication becomes the algorithm for the realization of the process of the subjectivization of work, a process which lies in the heart of postFordist productivity (Lohr & Nickel, 2005; Moldaschl & Voss, 2003; Schonberger & Springer, 2003). Yet critical psychology neither traces possible ruptures in the post-Fordist arrangement nor explores everyday forms of exodus and disobedience (Moulier Boutang, 1998; Virno, 2004). In other words, the critical psychological view of subjectication can elucidate, or diagnose, the productive role of the psychology in the social earthquake which accompanied the post-Fordist reorganization of labour and everyday sociality in North-Atlantic societies (Gordo-Lopez & Pujol Tarres, 2004; Papadopoulos, 2004). However, critical psychology is unable to engage with the suppressed potentialities of post-Fordist social relations which could lead to forms of political engagement that question post-Fordism itself (Karakayali & Tsianos, 2005; Negri, 1999; Santos, 2001; Stephenson, 2004). The reason for this is, as I argued above, that embodied subjectication is the core productive form of todays sociality. Embodied subjectication is not only a heuristic tool which enables social researchers to understand power relations in post-Fordist North-Atlantic societies, but also the very guarantor of what Weber (1978) calls legitimate domination. A form of domination which is actively and willingly performed differently by each individual and congeals a form of power, which, following Hannah Arendt (1970), emerges not as a means to dominate but by the very fact that people act together. Embodied subjectication (and its very theoreticization by governmentality studies) is a form of obedience to todays conguration of power in North-Atlantic societies. In this sense, micropolitics and embodied subjectication constitute a form of afrmative subjectivity in neoliberal and post-Fordist conditions. In ` the last part of the paper, I will briey discuss Jacques Rancieres concept of politics as a means for interfering in the production of afrmative subjectivity (for a more broad discussion of this issue s. Stephenson & Papadopoulos, 2006).

Interrupting afrmative subjectivity: Imperceptible politics


The opposition between micropolitics as the site of regulation and creativity and statepolitics or identity politics as normalizing and coercive no longer holds. This opposition has a wide ideological function which results from a particular reading of Foucault in which ethics is equated with politics, a very Eurocentric account indeed. There is a marked difference between claims about the politicization of everyday life and the assertion that we do politics through our very existence. If everything is political then nothing is. So while it is important to show, as Michel Foucault has done magnicently, that subjects are regulated through the micropractices of everyday life it is equally important to say that nothing is political in itself merely because power relationships are ` at work in it (Ranciere, 1998, p. 32). In order to interrupt and to overcome the production of afrmative subjectivity, a shift in our understanding of politics is needed. Here, I want to propose that politics has not primary to do with contesting given structures of domination by introducing new diversications of law, that is, rules of equality, the codication of rights and the cultivation of public responsibility. This seems to be a paradoxical proposition since rules of equality, rights and responsibility constitute an indispensable and plausible part of todays forms of active political engagement. However, in the following paragraphs I want to argue that following recent political philosophy we have the possibility to

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

155

understand why this law-oriented form of political engagement works in a different way than intended and ends up in crafting afrmative subjectivities. Thus, instead of this laworiented approach to political engagement I want to propose a justice-based approach ` (Benjamin, 1996; Honig, 1993). Following Ranciere (2001) and Badiou (2005), we can say that true politics is a collective enterprise which exposes a given social order to be limited, contingent and inconsistent. True politics attempts to include those who have no place in the normalizing organization of the existing social order. However, the placeless cannot be simply inserted by giving them a name (representation) and legal visibility (rights) in an existing social order (on the limits of the double-R axion, i.e. rights and representation, s. Papadopoulos & Tsianos, 2007). Inclusion through the granting of representation and rights does not question the structure of domination. Such inclusion only serves to acknowledge that a particular community or group really has no power to change the political order. A typical example of this is the proliferation of camps in modern societies. Consider the role of camps as part of the colonial legacy of Australia. The Indigenous population was interned in camps, missions and boarding schools. The extraordinary in these camps is that the Aboriginal population was included in the system of administration and regulation in order to become effaced and excluded. The exclusion of the Indigenous population took place through their inclusion in the system which controlled their whole existence and then systematically marginalized them. And todays exclusion of the Indigenous population is in fact the continuation of this complex exclusion/inclusion system of the older camps. With the detention centres, camps returned back to Australian normality (and of course not only to Australia!). And here we encounter the same phenomenon: detainees are included in the system of camps in order to facilitate their exclusion and often their forced deportation. The camp is much more than the place of exclusion par excellence. It is a very functional and necessary moment for the regulation of mobility and inclusion, but of course a very particular form of inclusion which targets the social control of the placeless and their mobility. Thus, we can say that racism and discrimination are not problems of exclusion, they are problems of inclusion. So, against the widespread position typically represented in Agambens work (1998) which regards the camp as total exclusion and as manifestation of the state of exception, here I want to assert that camps are symptomatic for exactly the opposite: their function is to include and to insert mobile populations into the existing forms of social and political control. Camps are social spaces which most drastically attempt to regulate the speed of the circulation of migrational movements and to include them in the global organization of labour (for a further elaboration of these points, see Andrijasevic, 2004; Ferrari Bravo, 2001; Papadopoulos, Stephenson, & Tsianos, 2008). Being included simply on the basis of a regulatory or egalitarian principle actually indicates that some parts of the society really have no role to play in governing. ` Democracy involves the inclusion of people who otherwise have no part (Ranciere, 1998). This necessitates a radically different form of inclusion, one which is not based on the legal inclusion of certain groups on the grounds of the representation of their difference. This leads to the obliteration of difference, since being included as different does not guarantee equal participation in government. Rather inclusion can only create truly equal social relations if it creates conditions where difference is not obliterated but becomes completely imperceptible (Deleuze & Guattari, 1987; Papadopoulos et al., 2008). What politics are normally thought to be is in fact nothing more than the site where the policing, standardizing, normalizing of difference functions through

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

156 Dimitris Papadopoulos

` visualization, representation and rights. For Ranciere (2000), policing produces a sensibility that can identify neither excess nor absence. The result is that society appears to be comprised of completely identiable, self-evident groups or parts of people who occupy the space that has been allocated to them and no other (cf. Stephenson & Kippax, 2006). I introduce here the concept of imperceptible politics as a possibility for breaking this form of policing. Politics (as opposed to policing) arises from the emergence of the miscounted, those who have no place and whose capacities remain imperceptible within the normalizing organization of the social realm. Refusing representation is a necessary move for doing politics from the position of those who have no part in community. Thus imperceptible politics does not refer to something which is invisible. Rather it refers to social forces which are outside existing regulation and outside policing. This approach to politics suggests that there is something important missing in the debates over the micropolitical or identitarian logic of constructivist, discursive and critical psychologies. Unless embodied subjectication interrupts policing, it is not politics. Unless subjectivity becomes committed to a collaborative, transformative and universal project which undermines the afrmation of the given order which regulates difference, it cannot address the issues of right and equality (Badiou, 2003). However, the factual involvement of micropolitics and identitarian politics in the consolidation of the neoliberal state proves the opposite. To do (true) politics necessitates disidentication and imperceptibility. Politics do not end with the afrmation of difference. They start from difference and entail a process of refusing who one is supposed to be. Doing politics regures the perceptible, not so others can nally recognize ones proper place in the social order, but to make evident the incommensurability of worlds, the incommensurability of inegalitarian distribution of bodies with the principle of equality. Politics, in this strict sense, is a refusal of representation. Politics happens outside of the performative production of embodied subjectivities. In other words, politics happens when reexivity is annulled and when processes of collective modication of the material conditions of our bodies and our perception are underway. Materialization has a particular importance for overcoming policing and afrmative subjectivity: it contests the notion that materiality is simply limited to the pervasive techniques of the body (e.g. Mauss, 1978) and the powers of discourse (e.g. Wilkinson & Kitzinger, 1996). Materialization commits to the practice of interrupting existing and installing new apparatuses of bodily production (Haraway, 1991a). Imperceptible politics entail working with collectively and materially organized imperceptible experience beyond reexivity, identity, and embodied subjectication. More than 20 years after the rst call to change the subject of psychology (Henriques et al., 1984) the subject has to change once again in order to incorporate imperceptible politics into the research strategies of alternative psychologies and to account for the social and political realities of North-Atlantic societies. The starting-point for this move could be an attempt to question the pervasiveness of representationalism (Derrida, 1978; Olkowski, 1999). Imperceptible politics call for moving away from representation as mediation between us as researchers and the social groups and social realities under study. This means challenging the rst function of representational: speaking-in-the-name-of (Spivak, 1999). The consequence of this is the restoration of the immediacy between research and the political-realities it refers to. But going beyond this rst sociopolitical function of representation, that is the speaking-in-the-name-of function, necessitates another one move, one which might be even more important for a project of critical social research

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

157

and social psychology. This second move is to overcome the epistemological function of representation: the belief that the objects under study be it in qualitative or quantitative form stand-in for a social reality behind them (Bauman, 1987). Overcoming the ubiquitous epistemology of stand-in means that our research is itself involved in an immanent and materialist transformation of the realities in which it takes place. Doing research in the ruins of representation (Olkowski, 1999) requires a reorganization of critical social science which follows but, nally, goes beyond the discursive, constructivist, and critical psychological positions. Such a research programme could develop along the following ve research trajectories: (1) Instead of investigating discursive and cultural representations, work with nonrepresentational, informal and imperceptible practices and experiences (Deleuze & Guattari, 1987; Papadopoulos et al., 2008). Instead of relying on reexivity for the creation of change, engage with affective transformations (Braidotti, 2002; Brown & Lunt, 2002; Brown & Stenner, 2001; Stephenson, 2004). Instead of focusing on subjective embodiment, explore processes of materialization which literally create new material actors (Barad, 2003; Haraway, 1997; Papadopoulos, 2005; Schraube, 2005; Whitehead, 1979). Instead of relying on the notion of subjectication, focus on continuous and dispersed forms of experience and multiplicity (Fraser, 1999; Irigaray, 1985; Middleton & Brown, 2005; Stephenson & Papadopoulos, 2006). Instead of considering sociality as a relational process, rethink suddenness and eventfulness in genuinely co-constructive and cooperative forms of sociality (Badiou, 2001; Haraway, 2003; Hardt & Negri, 2004; Lenin, 1978; Stengers, 2000).

(2)

(3)

(4)

(5)

References
Adorno, T. W. (1983). Negative dialectics. New York: Continuum. Agamben, G. (1998). Homo sacer: Sovereign power and bare life. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Anderson, B. (1991). Imagined communities: Reections on the origin and spread of nationalism. London: Verso. Andrijasevic, R. (2004). Trafciking in women and the politics of mobility in Europe. Department of Womens Studies, Utrecht University, Utrecht: Unpublished PhD dissertation. Arendt, H. (1970). The human condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Badiou, A. (2001). Ethics: An essay on the understanding of evil. London: Verso. Badiou, A. (2003). Saint Paul: The foundation of universalism. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Badiou, A. (2005). Metapolitics. London: Verso. Barad, K. (1998). Getting real: Technoscientic practices and the materialization of reality. Differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies, 10(2), 87126. Barad, K. (2003). Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how matter comes to matter. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 28(3), 801831. Bauman, Z. (1987). Legislators and interpreters: On modernity, post-modernity, and intellectuals. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bauman, Z. (1997). Postmodernity and its discontents. New York: New York University Press. Benjamin, W. (1996). Critique of violence. In W. Benjamin (Ed.), Selected writings, Vol. 1: 19131926 (pp. 236252). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

158 Dimitris Papadopoulos Bergson, H. (2001). Time and free will: An essay on the immediate data of consciousness. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications. Billig, M. (1991). Ideology and opinions: Studies in rhetorical psychology. London: Sage. Billig, M. (1996). Arguing and thinking: A rhetorical approach to social psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Billig, M. (1997). The dialogic unconscious: Psychoanalysis, discursive psychology and the nature of repression. British Journal of Social Psychology, 36, 139159. Blackman, L. (2000). Ethics, embodiment and the voice-hearing experience. Theory, Culture and Society, 17(5), 5574. Blackman, L., & Walkerdine, V. (2001). Mass hysteria: Critical psychology and media studies. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Bohrer, K. H. (1998). Plotzlichkeit. Zum Augenblick des asthetischen Scheins. Mit einem Nachwort von 1998. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. Bowring, F. (2002). Post-Fordism and the end of work. Futures, 34, 159172. Bradley, B. S. (1993). A serpents guide to childrens theories of mind. Theory and Psychology, 3(4), 497521. Bradley, B. S. (2005). The psychology of experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Braidotti, R. (2002). Metamorphoses: Towards a materialist theory of becoming. Cambridge; Malden, MA: Polity; Blackwell. Brown, S. D., & Lunt, P. (2002). A genealogy of the social identity tradition: Deleuze & Guattari and social psychology. British Journal of Social Psychology, 41, 123. Brown, S. D., & Stenner, P. (2001). Being affected: Spinoza and the psychology of emotion. International Journal of Group Tensions, 30(1), 81105. Bruner, J. S. (1990). Acts of meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Bruner, J. S. (1995). Meaning and self in cultural practice. In D. Bakhurst & C. Sypnowich (Eds.), The social self (pp. 1829). London: Sage. Burchell, G. (1996). Liberal government and techniques of the self. In A. Barry, T. Osborne, & N. Rose (Eds.), Foucault and political reason. Liberalism, neo-liberalism and rationalities of goverment (pp. 1936). London: University College London Press. Burman, E. (1994). Experience, identities and alliances: Jewish feminism and femist psychology. In K.-K. Bhavani & A. Phoenix (Eds.), Shifting identities-shifting racisms. A Feminism & psychology reader (pp. 155178). London: Sage. Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York: Routledge. Butler, J. (1997). Against proper objects. In E. Weed & N. Schor (Eds.), Feminism meets queer theory (pp. 130). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Cadava, E., Connor, P., & Nancy, J.-L. (Eds.). (1991). Who comes after the subject? London: Routledge. Clifford, J. (2000). Taking identity politics seriously: The contradictory, stony ground : : : . In P. Gilroy, L. Grossberg, & A. McRobbie (Eds.), Without guarantees: In honour of Stuart Hall (pp. 94112). London, New York: Verso. Clifford, J. (2001). Indigenous articulations. Contemporary Pacic, 13(2), 468490. Cole, M. (1996). Cultural psychology: A once and future discipline. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Connolly, W. E. (2002). Neuropolitics: Thinking, culture, speed. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Cote, J. E. (1996). Sociological perspectives on identity formation: The culture-identity link and identity capital. Journal of Adolescence, 19(5), 417428. Cote, J. E. (1997). An empirical test of the identity capital model. Journal of Adolescence, 20(5), 577597. Cote, J. E. (2000). Arrested adulthood: The changing nature of maturity and identity. New York: New York University Press.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

159

Csordas, T. J. (1994). Introduction: The body as representation and being-in-the-world. In T. J. Csordas (Ed.), Embodiment and experience: The existential ground of culture and self (pp. 124). Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press. Csordas, T. J. (1999). Embodiment and cultural phenomenology. In G. Weiss & H. F. Haber (Eds.), Perspectives on embodiment. The intersections of culture and nature (pp. 143162). London: Routledge. Danziger, K. (1997). Naming the mind. How psychology found its language. London: Sage. Davies, B., & Harre, R. (1990). Positioning: Conversation and the production of the selves. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior, 20, 4363. Dean, M. (1995). Governing the unemployed self in an active society. Economy and Society, 24(4), 559583. Dean, M. (1999). Governmentality: Power and rule in modern society. London: Sage. Deleuze, G. (1991). Was ist ein Dispositiv? In F. Ewald & B. Waldenfels (Eds.), Spiele der Wahrheit. Michel Foucaults Denken (pp. 153162). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Derrida, J. (1978). The theater of cruelty and the closure of representation. In J. Derrida (Ed.), Writing and difference (pp. 232250). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edwards, J. (1992). Language in group and individual identity. In G. M. E. Breakwell (Ed.), Social psychology of identity and the self concept (pp. 129146). London: Surrey University Press. Erikson, E. H. (1993). Childhood and society. New York: Norton. Fairbrother, P., & Rainnie, A. (Eds.). (2005). Globalisation, state and labour. London: Routledge. Ferrari Bravo, L. (2001). Dal fordismo alla globalizzazione. Cristalli di tempo politico. Roma: Manifestolibri. Fichtner, B. (1996). Lernen und Lerntatigkeit: Ontogenetische, phylogenetische und epistemologische Studien. Marburg: BdWI Verlag. Flowers, P. (2001). Gay men and HIV/AIDS risk management. Health, 5(1), 5075. Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. London: Penguin. Foucault, M. (1978). The history of sexuality. Vol.1: An introduction. London: Penguin. Foucault, M. (1984). What is an author? In P. Rabinow (Ed.), The Foucault reader (pp. 101120). New York: Pantheon Books. Foucault, M. (1987). The history of sexuality. Vol. 2: The use of pleasure. London: Penguin. Foucault, M. (1988). The ethic of care for the self as a practice of freedom. An interview with Michel Foucault on January 20, 1984. In J. W. Bernauer & D. M. Rasmussen (Eds.), The nal Foucault (pp. 120). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Foucault, M. (1990). The history of sexuality. Vol.3: The care of the self. London: Penguin. Foucault, M. (1994a). Warum ich Macht untersuche: Die Frage des Subjekts. In H. L. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow (Eds.), Michel Foucault. Jenseits von Strukturalismus und Hermeneutik (pp. 243250). Weinheim: Beltz Athenaum. Foucault, M. (1994b). Wie wird Macht ausgeubt? In H. L. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow (Eds.), Michel Foucault. Jenseits von Strukturalismus und Hermeneutik (pp. 251261). Weinheim: Beltz Athenaum. Foucault, M. (1994c). Zur Genealogie der Ethik: Ein Uberblick uber laufende Arbeiten. In H. L. Dreyfus & P. Rabinow (Eds.), Michel Foucault. Jenseits von Strukturalismus und Hermeneutik (pp. 265292). Weinheim: Beltz Athenaum. Fraser, M. (1999). Identity without selfhood: Simone de Beauvoir and bisexuality. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. Geertz, C. (1973). Dichte Beschreibung. Bemerkungen zu einer deutenden Theorie von Kultur. Gergen, K. J. (1990). Social understanding and the inscription of self. In J. W. Stigler, R. A. Shweder, & G. H. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural psychology: Essays on comparative human development (pp. 569602). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gergen, K. J. (1991). The saturated self: Dilemmas of identity in contemporary life. New York: Basic Books.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

160 Dimitris Papadopoulos Gergen, K. J. (1994). Realities and relationships: Soundings in social construction. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gergen, K. J. (1997). Theory under threat: Social construction and identity politics. In C. W. Tolman, F. Cherry, R. v. Hezewijk, & I. Lubek (Eds.), Problems of theoretical psychology (pp. 1323). Toronto: Captus University Publications. Gergen, K. J., & Gergen, M. M. (2002). Toward a cultural constructivist psychology. In M. Hildebrand-Nilshon, C.-W. Kim, & D. Papadopoulos (Eds.), Kultur (in) der Psychologie. Uber das Abenteuer des Kulturbegriffes in der psychologischen Theoriebildung (pp. 4764). Heidelberg: Asanger. Giddens, A. (1991). Modernity and self-identity. Self and society in the late modern age. Gill, R. (2006). Gender and the media. Cambridge: Polity Press. Gordo-Lopez, A. J., & Pujol Tarres, J. (2004). Intensifying psychological work: From geopolitical unresponsiveness to cultural rage/rave. International Journal of Critical Psychology, 12, 145161. Gorz, A. (2004). Wissen, Wert und Kapital: Zur Kritik der Wissensokonomie. Zurich: Rotpunktverlag. Groeben, N. (2006). Gibt es Wege aus der selbstverschuldeten Irrelevanz des qualitativen Offstreams? Forum: Qualitative Social Research, 7(4), Art. 34. http://www. qualitative-research.net/fqs-texte/34-06/06-34-34-d.htm. Hall, S. (1986a). Gramscis relevance for the study of race and ethnicity. Journal of Communication Inquiry, 10(2), 527. Hall, S. (1986b). On postmodernism and articulation. An interview with Stuart Hall. Journal of Communication Inquiry, 10(2), 4560. Hall, S. (1990). Cultural identity and Diaspora. In J. Rutherford (Ed.), Identity: Community, culture, difference (pp. 222237). London: Lawrence and Wishart. Hall, S. (1996). Introduction. Who needs identity? In S. Hall & P. d. Gay (Eds.), Questions of cultural identity (pp. 117). London: Sage. Hall, S., & du Gay, P. (Eds.). (1996). Questions of cultural identity. London: Sage. Haraway, D. J. (1988). Situated knowledges: The science question in feminism and the privilege of partial perspective. Feminist Studies, 14(3), 575599. Haraway, D. J. (1991a). The biopolitics of postmodern bodies: Constitutions of self in immune system discourse. In D. J. Haraway (Ed.), Simians, cyborgs, and women: The reinvention of nature (pp. 203230). New York: Routledge. Haraway, D. J. (1991b). Simians, cyborgs, and women: The reinvention of nature. New York: Routledge. Haraway, D. J. (1997). Modest_Witness@Second_Millennium. FemaleManq_Meets_OncoMousee: Feminism and technoscience. New York: Routledge. Haraway, D. J. (2003). The companion species manifesto: Dogs, people, and signicant otherness. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press. Hardt, M., & Negri, A. (2004). Multitude: War and democracy in the age of Empire. New York: The Penguin Press. Harre, R. (1983). Identity projects. In G. M. Breakwell (Ed.), Threatened identities (pp. 3151). New York: Wiley. Havighurst, R. J. (1972). Developmental tasks and education (3rd ed.). New York: McKay. Hayles, N. K. (1999). How we became posthuman: Virtual bodies in cybernetics, literature, and informatics. Chicago, Ill: University of Chicago Press. Henriques, J., Hollway, W., Urwin, C., Venn, C., & Walkerdine, V. (1984). Changing the subject: Psychology, social regulation and subjectivity. London: Methuen. Hildebrand-Nilshon, M., & Kim, C.-W. (2002). Zur Problematik des Wygotskischen Konzeptes der Zeichenvermitteltheit in Bezug auf die kulturpsychologische Herausforderung. In M. Hildebrand-Nilshon, C.-W. Kim, & D. Papadopoulos (Eds.), Kultur (in) der Psychologie. Uber das Abenteuer des Kulturbegriffes in der psychologischen Theoriebildung (pp. 195222). Heidelberg: Asanger.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

161

Hildebrand-Nilshon, M., Motzkau, J., & Papadopoulos, D. (2001). Reintegrating sense into subjectication. In J. R. Morss, N. Stephenson, & H. v. Rappard (Eds.), Theoretical issues in psychology (pp. 289300). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Holzkamp, K. (1983). Grundlegung der psychologie. Frankfurt [u.a.]: Campus-Verl. Holzkamp, K. (1987). Die Verkennung von Handlungsbegrundungen als empirische Zusammen hangsannahmen in sozialpsychologischen Theorien: Methodologische Fehlorientierung infolge von Begriffsverwirrung. Forum Kritische Psychologie, 19, 2358. Holzkamp, K. (1991). Experience of self and scientic objectivity. In C. W. Tolman & M. Wolfgang (Eds.), Critical psychology: Contributions to an historical science of the subject (pp. 6580). Cambridge, CA: Cambridge University Press. Holzkamp, K. (1992). On doing psyhology critically. Theory and Psychology, 2, 193204. Holzkamp, K. (1993). Lernen: Subjektwissenschaftliche Grundlegung. Frankfurt/Main: CampusVerlag. Holzkamp, K. (1996). Psychologie: Verstandigung uber Handlungsbegrundungen alltaglicher Lebensfuhrung. Forum Kritische Psychologie, 36, 7112. Honig, B. (1993). Political theory and the displacement of politics. Ithaca, NY; London: Cornell University Press. Irigaray, L. (1985). This sex which is not one. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Jessop, B. (2002). The future of the capitalist state. Cambridge: Polity Press. Karakayali, S., & Tsianos, V. (2005). Mapping the order of new migration. Undokumentierte Arbeit und die Autonomie der Migration. Peripherie, 97/98, 3564. Kelly, P. (2006). The entrepreneurial self and youth at-risk: Exploring the horizons of identity in the twenty-rst century. Journal of Youth Studies, 9(1), 1732. Keupp, H. (Ed.). (1997). Identitatsarbeit heute: Klassische und aktuelle Perspektiven der Identitatsforschung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Kippax, S., & Race, K. (2003). Sustaining safe practice: Twenty years on. Social Science and Medicine, 57, 112. Kraus, E. M. (1998). The metaphysics of experience: A companion to Whiteheads process and reality (2nd ed.). New York: Fordham University Press. Kroger, J. (1996). Identity in adolescence: The balance between self and other (2nd ed.). London: Routledge. Kvale, S. (1977). Lernpsychologie als Ideologie und Technologie. Psychologie and Gesellschaft, 3/4, 143175. Laclau, E., & Mouffe, C. (1985). Hegemony and socialist strategy: Towards a radical democratic politics. London: Verso. Latour, B. (2004). How to talk about the body? The normative dimension of science studies. Body and Society, 10(23), 205229. Lazzarato, M. (2002). Videophilosophie. Zeitwahrnehmung im Postfordismus. Berlin: b_books. Lenin, V. I. (1978). What is to be done? Burning questions of our movement. Moscow: Progress Publishers. Leontjew, A. N. (1977). Probleme der Entwicklung des Psychischen. Kronberg/Ts: Athenaum Verl. Lohr, K., & Nickel, H. (2005). Subjektivierung von Arbeit - riskante Chancen. Munster: Westfalisches Dampfboot. Luhmann, N. (1995). Social systems. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Marazzi, C. (1998). Der Stammplatz der Socken. Die linguistische Wende der Okonomie und ihre Auswirkungen in der Politik. Zurich: Seismo Verlag. Marcia, J. E. (1993a). The ego identity status approach to ego identity. In J. E. Marcia, A. S. Waterman, D. R. Matteson, S. L. Archer, & J. L. Ortofsky (Eds.), Ego identity. A handbook for psychological research (pp. 321). New York: Springer. Marcia, J. E. (1993b). The status of the statuses: Research review. In J. E. Marcia, A. S. Waterman, D. R. Matteson, S. L. Archer, & J. L. Ortofsky (Eds.), Ego identity. A handbook for psychological research (pp. 2241). New York: Springer.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

162 Dimitris Papadopoulos Marvakis, A., & Papadopoulos, D. (2002). Vom Universalismus zum kulturellen Reduktionismus? Die meteorische Blute der Kulturpsychologie und ihre zukunftige Aussichten. In M. Hildebrand-Nilshon, C.-W. Kim, & D. Papadopoulos (Eds.), Kultur (in) der Psychologie. Uber das Abenteuer des Kulturbegriffes in der psychologischen Theoriebildung (pp. 139160). Heidelberg: Asanger. Mauss, M. (1978). Der Begriff der Technik des Korpers. In M. Mauss (Ed.), Soziologie und Anthropologie. Band II: Gabentausch, Todesvorstellung, Korpertechniken. Frankfurt/M: Ullstein. Middleton, D., & Brown, S. (2005). The social psychology of experience: Studies in remembering and forgetting. London: Sage. Moldaschl, M., & Voss, G. G. (Eds.). (2003). Subjektivierung von Arbeit. Munchen: Hampp. Moulier Boutang, Y. (1998). De lesclavage au salariat. Economie historique du salariat bride. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. Moulier Boutang, Y. (2003). Neue Grenzziehungen in der Politischen Okonomie. In M. Von Osten (Ed.), Norm der Abweichung (pp. 251280). Wien/New York: Springer, Edition Voldemeer Zurich. Negri, A. (1999). Insurgencies: Constituent power and the modern state. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Neilson, B., & Rossiter, N. (2005). From precarity to precariousness and back again: Labour, life and unstable networks. Fibreculture, 5, from http://journal.breculture.org/issue5/ neilson_rossiter.html. Olkowski, D. (1999). Gilles Deleuze and the ruin of representation. Berkeley, CA; London: University of California Press. Papadopoulos, D. (1999). Lew S. Wygotski. Werk und Wirkung. Frankfurt/Main: Campus Verlag. Papadopoulos, D. (2002). Dialectics of subjectivity. North-Atlantic certainties, neo-liberal rationality, and liberation promises. International Journal of Critical Psychology, 6, 99122. Papadopoulos, D. (2003). The ordinary superstition of subjectivity. Liberalism and technostructural violence. Theory and Psychology, 13(1), 7393. Papadopoulos, D. (2004). Editorial: Psychology and the political. International Journal of Critical Psychology, 12, 513. Papadopoulos, D. (2005). For a new materialist understanding of social science: Decomposing the fact-value debate. In A. H. A. Gulerce, I. Steauble, G. Saunders, & J. Kay (Eds.), Contemporary theorizing in psychology: Global perspectives (pp. 3947). Concord, ON: Captus Press. Papadopoulos, D. (2006). World 2. On the signicance and impossibility of articulation. Culture, Theory and Critique, 47(2), 165179. Papadopoulos, D. & Tsianos, V. (2007). How to do sovereignty without people? Boundary 2, 34(1), 135172. Papadopoulos, D., Stephenson, N., & Tsianos, V. (2008). Escape! Power and revolt in the 21st century. London: Pluto Press. Parker, I. (1992). Discourse dynamics: Critical analysis for social and individual psychology. London: Routledge. Parker, I. (2005). Qualitative psychology: Introducing radical research. Maidenhead: Open University Press. Politzer, G. (1929). Kritik der klassischen Psychologie. Koln: Europaische Verlagsanstalt, 1974. Potter, J., & Wetherell, M. (1987). Discourse and social psychology: Beyond attitudes and behaviour. London: Sage Publications. Race, K. (2001). The undetectable crisis: Changing technologies of risk. Sexualities, 4(2), 167189. ` Ranciere, J. (1998). Disagreement: Politics and philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ` ` Ranciere, J. (2000). Dissenting words: A conversation with Jacques Ranciere. Diacritics, 30, 113126. ` Ranciere, J. (2001). Ten theses on politics. Theory and Event, 5(3), 1734.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

163

Riessman, C. K. (1993). Narrative analysis. London: Sage. Rose, N. (1989). Individualizing psychology. In J. Shotter & K. J. Gergen (Eds.), Texts of identity (pp. 119132). London: Sage. Rose, N. (1996a). Identity, genealogy, history. In S. Hall & P. d. Gay (Eds.), Questions of cultural identity (pp. 128150). London: Sage. Rose, N. (1996b). Inventing our selves. Psychology, power and personhood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rosengarten, M. (2004). Consumer activism in the pharmacology of HIV. Body and Society, 10(1), 91107. Rubinstein, S. L. (1977). Sein und Bewutsein. Die Stellung des Psychischen im allgemeinen Zusammenhang der Erscheinungen in der materiellen Welt. Berlin, GDR: Akademie Verlag. Santos, B. d. S. (2001). Nuestra America: Reinventing a subaltern paradigm of recognition and redistribution. Theory, Culture and Society, 18(2/3), 185218. Sassen, S. (1999). A new emergent hegemonic structure? Political Power and Social Theory, 13, 277289. Scarry, E. (1985). The body in pain: The making and unmaking of the world. New York: Oxford University Press. Schonberger, K., & Springer, S. (Eds.). (2003). Subjektivierte Arbeit: Mensch, Organisation und Technik in einer entgrenzten Arbeitswelt. Frankfurt/Main: Campus-Verl. Schraube, E. (1998). Auf den Spuren der Dinge: Psychologie in einer Welt der Technik (1. Au. ed.). Berlin: Argument-Verlag. Schraube, E. (2005). Torturing things until they confess. Gunther Anderss critique of technology. Science as Culture, 14(1), 7785. Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press. Selby, J. M., & Bradley, B. S. (2003). Infants in groups: A paradigm for the study of early social experience. Human Development, 46(4), 197221. ` Seve, L. (1977). Marxismus und Theorie der Personlichkeit (3. Au. ed.). Frankfurt/M: Verl. Marxistische Blatter. Seymour-Smith, S., Wetherell, M., & Phoenix, A. (2002). My wife ordered me to come!: A discursive analysis of doctors and nurses accounts of mens use of general practitioners. Journal of Health Psychology, 7(3), 253267. Shotter, J. (1993a). Becoming someone: Identity and belonging. In J. F. Nussbaum & N. Coupland (Eds.), Discourse and lifespan identity (pp. 527). London: Sage. Shotter, J. (1993b). Conversational realities: Constructing life through language. London: Sage Publications. Shotter, J., & Gergen, K. J. (Eds.). (1989). Texts of identity. London: Sage. Shweder, R. A. (1991). Thinking through cultures: Expeditions in cultural psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Simondon, G. (1992). The genesis of the individual. In J. Crary & S. Kwinter (Eds.), Incorporations (pp. 297319). New York, NY: Zone. Slack, J. D. (1996). The theory and method of articulation in cultural studies. In D. Morley & K.-H. Chen (Eds.), Stuart Hall. Critical dialogues in cultural studies (pp. 112127). London: Routledge. Smedslund, J. (1988). Psycho-Logic. New York: Springer. Spivak, G. C. (1999). A critique of postcolonial reason: Toward a history of the vanishing present. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Stengers, I. (2000). The invention of modern science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Stenner, P. (2004). Psychology and the Political: On the psychology of natural right and the political origins of modern psychology. International Journal for Critical Psychology, 12, 1437. Stenner, P. (2005). Emotions and rights: On the interpenetration of the psychic and the social. In A. H. A. Gulerce, I. Steauble, G. Saunders, & J. Kay (Eds.), Contemporary theorizing in psychology: Global perspectives (pp. 139148). Concord, ON: Captus Press.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

164 Dimitris Papadopoulos Stephenson, N. (2003). Interrupting neo-liberal subjectivities. Continuum: Journal of Media and Cultural Studies, 17(2), 135146. Stephenson, N. (2004). Elaborating sociability: The mattering of unspeakable excess. International Journal of Critical Psychology, 12, 162186. Stephenson, N., & Kippax, S. (2006). Transguring relations: Theorizing political change in the everyday. Theory and Psychology, 16(3), 391415. Stephenson, N., & Papadopoulos, D. (2006). Analysing everyday experience. Social research and political change. London: Palgrave Macmillan. Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of modern identity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Teo, T. (2005). The critique of psychology: From Kant to postcolonial theory. New York: Springer. Tolman, C. W. (1991). Theoretical indeterminacy, Pluralism and the conceptual concrete. Theory and Psychology, 12, 147162. Toulmin, S., & Leary, D. E. (1985). The cult of empiricism and beyond. In S. Koch & D. E. Leary (Eds.), A century of psychology as science (pp. 594617). New York: McGraw-Hill. Virno, P. (2004). A grammar of the multitude. Los Angeles: Semiotext(e). Vygotskij, L. S. (1996). Die Lehre von den Emotionen: Eine psychologiehistorische Untersuchung. Munster: Lit. Vygotsky, L. S. (1929). [Concrete human psychology]. Soviet Psychology, 1989, 27, 5377. Vygotsky, L. S. (1934). Thinking and speech. In R. W. Rieber & A. C. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of L.S. Vygotsky. Bd. 1: Problems of general psychology (pp. 39285). New York: Plenum. Walkerdine, V. (1984). Developmental psychology and the child centered pedagogy: The insertion of Piaget in early education. In J. Henriques, W. Hollway, C. Urwin, C. Venn, & V. Walkerdine (Eds.), Changing the subject: Psychology, social regulation and subjectivity (pp. 153202). London: Methuen. Walkerdine, V. (1997). Daddys girl: Young girls and popular culture. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wallerstein, I. M. (1998). Utopistics, or, historical choices of the twenty-rst century. New York: The New Press. Warner, M. (2002). Publics and counterpublics. New York: Zone Books. Weber, M. (1978). Economy and society: An outline of interpretive sociology. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Wellmer, A. (1991). Endspiele: Die unversohnliche Moderne. Essays und Vortrage. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp. Wertsch, J. V. (1991). Voices of the mind. A sociocultural approach to mediated action. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Wetherell, M. (1996). Life histories/social histories. In M. Wetherell (Ed.), Identities, groups and social issues (pp. 300339). London: Sage. Wetherell, M. (1998). Positioning and interpretative repertoires. Conversation analysis and poststructuralism in dialogue. Discourse and Society, 9, 387412. White, S. H. (1996). The relationship of developmental psychology to social policy. In E. F. Zigler, S. L. Kagan, et al. (Eds.), Children, families, and government: Preparing for the twenty-rst century (pp. 409426). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Whitehead, A. N. (1979). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology (Corrected/edited by David Ray Grifn and Donald W. Sherburne ed.). New York: Free Press. Wilkinson, S., & Kitzinger, C. (1996). Feminism and discourse. London: Sage. Williams, F. (1994). Social relations, welfare and the post-Fordism debate. In R. Burrows & B. Loader (Eds.), Towards a post-Fordist welfare state? (pp. 4973). London: Rouledge. Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations. New York: Prentice Hall. Wulf, C. (2004). Anthropologie: Geschichte, Kultur, Philosophie. Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt Taschenbuch Verlag.

Copyright The British Psychological Society


Reproduction in any form (including the internet) is prohibited without prior permission from the Society

In the ruins of representation

165

Wygotski, L. S. (1930). Die psychischen Systeme. In L. S. Wygotski (Ed.), Ausgewahlte Schriften. Bd. 1: Arbeiten zu theoretischen und methodologischen Problemen der Psychologie. (pp. 319352). Koln: Pahl-Rugenstein, 1985. Wygotski, L. S. (1931). Geschichte der hoheren psychischen Funktionen. Munster: 1992. Yoder, A. E. (2000). Barriers to ego identity status formation: A contextual qualication of Marcias identity status paradigm. Journal of Adolescence, 23(1), 95106. Received 25 July 2005; revised version received 24 January 2007

You might also like